Skip to content
BY-NC-ND 3.0 license Open Access Published by De Gruyter September 28, 2013

Neuropragmatism, knowledge, and pragmatic naturalism

  • John Shook
From the journal Human Affairs

Abstract

Neuropragmatism is a research program taking sciences about cognitive development and learning methods most seriously, in order to reevaluate and reformulate philosophical issues. Knowledge, consciousness, and reason are among the crucial philosophical issues directly affected. Pragmatism in general has allied with the science-affirming philosophy of naturalism. Naturalism is perennially tested by challenges questioning its ability to accommodate and account for knowledge, consciousness, and reason. Neuropragmatism is in a good position to evaluate those challenges. Some ways to defuse them are suggested here, along with recommendations about the specific kind of naturalism, a pluralistic and perspectival naturalism, that neuropragmatism should endorse.

[1] Baker, L. (2013). Naturalism and the First-Person Perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Search in Google Scholar

[2] Berthoz, A. and Christen, Y. (2008). Neurobiology of “Umwelt”: How Living Beings Perceive the World. New York: Springer. Search in Google Scholar

[3] Cartwright, N. (1989). Nature’s Capacities and Their Measurement. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Search in Google Scholar

[4] Cartwright, N. (1999). The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139167093Search in Google Scholar

[5] Casullo, A. (2003). A Priori Justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/0195115058.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

[6] Churchland, P. (2012). Plato’s Camera: How the Physical Brain Captures a Landscape of Abstract Universals. Cambridge, UK: MIT Press. Search in Google Scholar

[7] Coffa, J. A. (1993). The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Search in Google Scholar

[8] Cohen, J. and Matthen, M. (Eds.). (2010). Color Ontology and Color Science. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Search in Google Scholar

[9] Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Co. Search in Google Scholar

[10] Dewey, J. (1925). Experience and Nature. Chicago: Open Court. Search in Google Scholar

[11] Dewey, J. (1938). Logic: The Theory of Inquiry. New York: Henry Holt. Search in Google Scholar

[12] Ernest, P. (1998). Social Constructivism as a Philosophy of Mathematics. Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York Press. Search in Google Scholar

[13] Flanagan, O. and Martin, S. (2012). Science and the Modest Image of Epistemology. Humana. Mente Journal of Philosophical Studies 21, 123–148. Search in Google Scholar

[14] Galison, P. and Daston, L. (2007). Objectivity. Boston: Zone Books. Search in Google Scholar

[15] Gallagher, S. and Miyahara, K. (2012). Neo-Pragmatism and Enactive Intentionality. In J. Schulkin (Ed.). Action, Perception and the Brain, pp. 117–146. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan. Search in Google Scholar

[16] Gallagher, S. and Zahavi, D. (2012). The Phenomenological Mind, 2nd edition. London and New York: Routledge. Search in Google Scholar

[17] Gonza lez, W. (Ed.) (2011). Scientific Realism and Democratic Society: The Philosophy of Philip Kitcher. Amsterdam and New York: Rodopi. Search in Google Scholar

[18] Grattan-Guinness, I. (2000). The Rainbow of Mathematics: A History of the Mathematical Sciences. New York: W. W. Norton. Search in Google Scholar

[19] Haack, S. (1996). Deviant Logic, Fuzzy Logic: Beyond the Formalism, 2nd edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Search in Google Scholar

[20] Hankinson, R. J. (1995). The Sceptics. London and New York: Routledge. Search in Google Scholar

[21] Hanna, R. and Maiese, M. (2009). Embodied Minds in Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Search in Google Scholar

[22] Hardin, C. L. (1988). Color for Philosophers: Unweaving the Rainbow, 2nd edition. Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett. Search in Google Scholar

[23] Horst, S. (2007). Beyond Reduction: Philosophy of Mind and Post-Reductionist Philosophy of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Search in Google Scholar

[24] Jenkins, C. (2008). Grounding Concepts: An Empirical Basis for Arithmetical Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199231577.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

[25] Kim, J. (2007). Physicalism, or Something Near Enough. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. Search in Google Scholar

[26] Kitcher, P. (1984). The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Search in Google Scholar

[27] Maddy, P. (1997). Naturalism in Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Search in Google Scholar

[28] Nagel, Th. (1986). The View from Nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Search in Google Scholar

[29] Pincock, C. (2012). Mathematics and Scientific Representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199757107.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

[30] Price, H. (2013). Pluralism, “World” and the Primacy of Science. In H. Price et al. Expressivism, Pragmatism and Representationalism, pp. 45–64. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511842498.005Search in Google Scholar

[31] Putnam, H. (1999). The Threefold Cord: Mind, Body, and World. New York: Columbia University Press. Search in Google Scholar

[32] Quine, W. V. (1980). On What There Is. In W. V. Quine. From a Logical Point of View, 2nd edition. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Search in Google Scholar

[33] Searle, J. (1992). The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Search in Google Scholar

[34] Shook, J. (2011). Varieties of Twentieth Century American Naturalism. The Pluralist 6:2, 1–17. http://dx.doi.org/10.5406/pluralist.6.2.0001Search in Google Scholar

[35] Shook, J. (2012). Social Cognition and the Problem of Other Minds. In D. Franks and J. Turner. Handbook of Neurosociology, pp. 33–46. New York: Springer, 2012. Search in Google Scholar

[36] Shook, J. (2014 forthcoming). Is Experience Naturally Objective or Subjective, or Both? In J. Shook and T. Solymosi. (Eds.). Pragmatist Neurophilosophy: American Philosophy and the Brain. London: Bloomsbury Academic. Search in Google Scholar

[37] Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008). Is Moral Phenomenology Unified? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7, 85–97. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11097-007-9065-zSearch in Google Scholar

[38] Solymosi, T. and Shook, J. (2013). Neuropragmatism: A Neurophilosophical Manifesto. European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 5:1, 212–233. Search in Google Scholar

[39] Stewart, J., Gapenne, O. and Di Paolo, E. (Eds.). (2010). Enaction: Towards a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Search in Google Scholar

[40] Thompson, E. (2003). Colour Vision: A Study in Cognitive Science and Philosophy of Science. London and New York: Routledge. Search in Google Scholar

Published Online: 2013-09-28
Published in Print: 2013-10-01

© 2013 Institute for Research in Social Communication, Slovak Academy of Sciences

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 License.

Downloaded on 2.6.2024 from https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.2478/s13374-013-0150-4/html
Scroll to top button