Skip to main content
Log in

RETRACTED ARTICLE: Contrasting Embodied Cognition with Standard Cognitive Science: A Perspective on Mental Representation

  • Published:
Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This article was retracted on 04 September 2020

This article has been updated

Abstract

The proponents of embodied cognition often try to present their research program as the next step in the evolution of standard cognitive science. The domain of standard cognitive science is fairly clearly circumscribed (perception, memory, attention, language, problem solving, learning). Its ontological commitments, that is, its commitments to various theoretical entities, are overt: cognition involves algorithmic processes upon symbolic representations. As a research program, embodied cognition exhibits much greater latitude in subject matter, ontological commitment, and methodology than does standard cognitive science. The proponents of embodied cognition to explain the aspects of human cognition are using the importance of embodied interaction with the environment, which is a dynamic relation. The cause of disagreement between these two approaches is regarding the role assumed by the notion of representation. The discussion about the contrast between embodied cognition and standard cognitive science is incomplete without Gibson’s ecological theory of perception and connectionist account of cognition. I will briefly contrast these important theories with computational view of cognition, highlighting the debate over role of representation. Embodied cognition has incorporated rather extensively a variety of insights emerging from research both in ecological psychology and in connectionism. The way I have followed to contrast embodied cognition with standard cognitive science, involves concentration on those several themes that appear to be prominent in the body of work that is often seen as illustrative of embodied cognition. This strategy has the advantage of postponing hard questions about “the” subject matter, ontological commitments, and methods of embodied cognition until more is understood about the particular interests and goals that embodied cognition theorists often pursue. This approach might show embodied cognition to be poorly unified, suggesting that the embodied cognition label should be abandoned in favor of several labels that reflect more accurately the distinct projects that have been clumped together under a single title. Alternatively, it might show that, in fact, there are some overarching commitments that bring tighter unity to the various bodies of work within embodied cognition that seem thematically only loosely related. The contrast between these two approaches is highlighted not only the basis of a priori argument but major experiments have been mentioned, to show the weight of the assumptions of both the contrasting approaches.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Change history

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. Hoboken: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2009). Why the mind is still in the head. In P. Robbins & M. Aydede (Eds.), Cambridge handbook of situated cognition (pp. 78–95). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Anderson, M. L. (2003). Embodied cognition: A field guide. Artificial Intelligence, 149(1), 91–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beer, R. D. (2014). Dynamical systems and embedded cognition. In K. Frankish & W. Ramsey (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of artificial intelligence (pp. 128–148). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Block, N. (2005). Action in perception by Alva Noë. The Journal of Philosophy, 102(5), 259–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. A. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47(1–3), 139–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cacioppo, J. T., Priester, J. R., & Berntson, G. G. (1993). Rudimentary determinants of attitudes: II. Arm flexion and extension have differential effects on attitudes. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65(1), 5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1990). Syntactic transformations on distributed representations. Connection Science, 2, 53–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. 1993). Connectionism and compositionality: why fodor and pylyshyn were wrong. Philosophical Psychology, 6, 305–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, M., & Bargh, J. A. (1999). Consequences of automatic evaluation: Immediate behavioral predispositions to approach or avoid the stimulus. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 25(2), 215–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J., & Pylyshyn, Z. (1981). How direct is visual perception? some reflections on gibson’s ecological approach. Cognition, 9, 139–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A., & Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: a critical analysis. Cognition, 28(1–2), 3–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gabarini, F., & Adenzato, M. (2004). At the root of embodied cognition: Cognitive science meets neurophysiology. Brain and Cognition, 56, 100–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., & Lakoff, G. (2005). The brain’s concepts: The role of the sensory-motor system in reason and language. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 22, 455–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1966). The senses considered as perceptual systems. Prospect Heights: Waveland Press, Inc.

  • Gibson, J. J. (2014). The ecological approach to visual perception: Classic edition. New York: Psychology Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glenberg, A. M., & Kaschak, M. P. (2002). Grounding language in action. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 9(3), 558–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, R. (1972). Seeing as thinking: an active theory of perception. London Times Literary Supplement, 23, 707–708.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harnad, S. (1990). The symbol grounding problem. Physica D: Nonlinear Phenomena, 42(1–3), 335–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. L. (2002). Consciousness in action. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the flesh: the embodied mind and its challenge to western thought (Vol. 4). New York: Basic Books.

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (2008). Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr, D., & Poggio, T. (1976). Cooperative computation of stereo disparity. Science, 194, 283–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A., & Simon, H. (1961). Computer simulation of human thinking. Science, 134, 2011–2017.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niedenthal, P. M., Barsalou, L. W., Winkielman, P., Krauth-Gruber, S., & Ric, F. (2005). Embodiment in attitudes, social perception, and emotion. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 9(3), 184–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, J., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 939–1031.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W., Stich, S., & Rumelhart, D. (Eds.). (1991). Philosophy and connectionist theory. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., & Craighero, L. (2004). The mirror-neuron system. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 27, 169–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenfeld, A. (1988). Computer vison: basic principles. Proceedings of the IEEE, 76, 863–868.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (2007). The embodied cognition research programme. Philosophy Compass, 2, 338–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (2010). Embodied cognition. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sternberg, S. (1969). Memory scanning: Mental processes revealed by reaction-time experiments. American Scientist, 57, 421–457.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thelen, E., & Smith, L. (1994). A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation? The Journal of Philosophy, 92(7), 345–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, M. (2002). Six views of embodied cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 9(4), 625–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. (2004). Boundaries of the mind. The individual in the fragile sciences: Cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R., & Clark, A. (2009). How to situate cognition: Letting nature take its course. In P. Robbins & M. Aydede (Eds.), Cambridge handbook of situated cognition (pp. 55–77). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pankaj Singh.

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Singh, P. RETRACTED ARTICLE: Contrasting Embodied Cognition with Standard Cognitive Science: A Perspective on Mental Representation. J. Indian Counc. Philos. Res. 36, 125–149 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-018-0159-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-018-0159-5

Keywords

Navigation