Skip to main content
Log in

Alon Harel on How to Deliberate Permissibly

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Criminal Law and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Alon Harel defines extreme cases as those in which the only way to avert a destructive threat is to harm innocent people. He rejects traditional consequentialist and non-consequentialist approaches because of the type of reasoning they both employ. I interpret Harel as making two central objections to this form of reasoning. First, traditional approaches require comparisons to be made about the value of human life. Second, decisions in extreme cases, even if permissible, should not be made under the guidance of rules. I argue that these objections, though prima facie plausible, are on reflection relatively weak, and I offer instead a more moderate argument that vindicates Harel’s general thesis that deliberation is morally relevant. More specifically, I argue that whether one acts on certain conditions affects both the moral permissibility of one’s actions and the duties owed by others.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Arguably the rejection of the relevance of intentions is not entailed by the core commitment of consequentialism as intentions may contribute value to states of affairs. Compare two worlds where everyone does the same thing outwardly, but in world 1 they have bad intentions whereas in world 2 they have good intentions. A consequentialist could argue that, given a necessary choice between the two, it would be impermissible to bring about world 1 on the ground that it is less valuable than world 2.

  2. See Thomson et al. (1991), Kamm (2007), and Scanlon (2008).

  3. Harel (2014, 199).

  4. Although Harel attributes this claim to consequentialists, not all consequentialists believe this. See Portmore (2011).

  5. For example, Nozick (1974).

  6. For discussion of this distinction, see Quinn (1989), Bennett (1995) and McMahan (1993).

  7. For discussion of this distinction, see Quinn (1993) and McMahan (2009, 170–173). The terminology is due to Tadros (2013, Chapter 11).

  8. Harel (2014, 108).

  9. Ibid. 111.

  10. Ibid. 123.

  11. Ibid.

  12. A positive comparative judgment specifies the way in which two items compare according to some value rather than the way in which they do not compare. For example, the claim that George Eliot is better than Charles Dickens in terms of literary quality is a positive comparison, whilst the claim that Dickens is worse than Eliot in terms of literary value is a negative comparison. See Chang (2002).

  13. Harel (2014, 122).

  14. Ibid. 121.

  15. Ibid. 122.

  16. Ibid.

  17. See Dancy (2004, especially Chapter 5).

  18. Of course, there are those who deny that torture is ever permissible. See, for example, Gaita (2002).

  19. Harel (2014, 118).

  20. Ibid. 118.

  21. Ibid. 122.

  22. For an elaboration of this idea, see Kamm (2007, Chapter 7).

  23. This case is taken from Tadros (2013, 159).

  24. I thank Victor Tadros for discussions about this possibility.

  25. This example is modified from Parr and Slavny, ‘Harmless Discrimination’ (forthcoming in Legal Theory).

  26. See Scheffler (1992).

  27. Rawls (1964).

  28. Nozick (1974, 94).

  29. Dworkin (1986, 194). For a Dworkinian argument that third parties who benefit from the positive externalities of procreation are not required to share the costs with those who decide to reproduce, see Casal and Williams (2004, 150–169).

  30. Casal and Willaims (2004, 159).

  31. See Tadros (2013, 122–127 and 149–155).

References

  • Bennett, Jonathan. The Act Itself (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995).

    Google Scholar 

  • Casal, Paula, and Andrew Williams. “Equality of Resources and Procreative Justice” in Justine Burley (Ed.) Dworkin and his Critics (Blackwell, 2004).

  • Chang, Ruth. “The Possibility of Parity” Ethics 112(4) (2002), 659–688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, Jonathan. Ethics Without Principles (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. Law’s Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaita, Raymond. A Common Humanity: Thinking about Love, Truth and Justice (Routledge, New Edition 2002).

  • Harel, Alon. Why Law Matters (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, Francis. Intricate Ethics: Rights, Responsibilities, and Permissible Harm (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, Jeff. “Killing, Letting Die and Withdrawing Aid” Ethics 103(2) (1993), 250–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, Jeff. Killing in War (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, Robert. Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Basic Books, 1974).

  • Parr, Tom, and Adam Slavny, “Harmless Discrimination” forthcoming in Legal Theory.

  • Portmore, Douglas. Common Sense Consequentialism: Where Morality Meets Rationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quinn, Warren. “Actions, Intentions, and Consequences: The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing” Philosophical Review 98(3) (1989), 287–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quinn, Warren. “Actions, Intentions, and Consequences: The Doctrine of Double Effect” in Morality and Action (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. “Legal Obligation and the Duty of Fair Play” in Sidney Hook (Ed.) Law and Philosophy (New York: New York University Press, 1964).

  • Scanlon, T. M. Moral Dimensions: Permissibility, Meaning, Blame (Cambridge, MASS: Harvard University Press, 2008).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, Samuel. Human Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992).

    Google Scholar 

  • Tadros, Victor. The Ends of Harm: The Moral Foundations of Criminal Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013).

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, Judith Jarvis. “Self Defense” Philosophy and Public Affairs 20 (1991), 283–310.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Victor Tadros for comments on this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Adam Slavny.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Slavny, A. Alon Harel on How to Deliberate Permissibly. Criminal Law, Philosophy 11, 833–846 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-015-9384-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-015-9384-z

Keywords

Navigation