Skip to main content
Log in

An Overarching Framework for Understanding and Explaining Human Nature

  • ORIGINAL ARTICLE
  • Published:
Biological Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article investigates how we can reconcile conceptions of human nature with biological explanations. Therefore, it discusses essential differences between (neo) Cartesian substance dualism and (neo) Aristotelian substance monism. It argues that only the (neo) Aristotelian conception of the psuchē, as the set of potentialities the exercise of which is characteristic of the organism, is coherent. The question of how we can reconcile this conception with biological explanations is answered by discussing how it can be integrated with Tinbergen’s subdivision of causal explanations into two proximate and two ultimate explanations, and with modern evolutionary theory. The use of the resulting overarching framework is illustrated by discussing its application to empirical phenomena.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A well-known example illustrating this point is the result of investigations by Pittendrigh (1958). He studied how an insect (Drosophila) emerged from its pupa stage and asked why it occurs in the early morning. The ultimate explanation or function is humidity: insects emerge in the early morning from their pupa stage when humidity is high for this optimizes, for example, unfolding and stretching of the wings and therefore increases survival. However, Pittendrigh showed that the proximate, immediate explanation is not humidity. The proximate explanation turned out to be the shift from light to dark: this shift affects an internal clock mechanism so that insects emerge from the pupa during the early morning when humidity is high.

  2. Powers of animate things are attributes of space-occupying organisms. They are not made of stuffs as material objects are, although they have a physical basis for possession of powers (just as the power of hydrochloric acid to burn a hole in a shirt is not made of HCl but is only due to it, and the horsepower of a car is not made of cylinders or steel: these are its physical basis).

  3. If we have acquired knowing that, we have acquired information. Such information may be before one’s mind (when we are conscious that things are so), brought to mind (we are then already aware that things are so), or it may have slipped one’s mind (we need to call it to mind or be reminded that things are so).

  4. Humans, as language users, possess over and above the nutritive and sensitive psuchē a rational psuchē. Notice that this does not mean that they possess three psuchē–s, but that the distinctive set of human powers includes the essential powers of vegetal and animal forms of life.

  5. This ultimate explanation is an extension of the one given by Wulf and Grete Schiefenhövel and was suggested by the reviewer.

References

  • Ayala FJ (2007) Darwin’s greatest discovery: design without designer. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 104(Suppl 1):8567–8573

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett MR, Hacker PMS (2022) Philosophical foundations of neuroscience, revised 2nd edn. Wiley, Chichester

    Google Scholar 

  • Burt EA ([1932]2003) The metaphysical foundations of modern science, revised 2nd edn. Dover Publications, New York

  • Darwin C ([1859]1968) On the origin of species by means of natural selection. Penguin Books, Harmondsworth

  • Dawkins R (1986) The blind watchmaker. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene S (2014) Consciousness and the brain: deciphering how the brain codes our thoughts. Penguin Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (1990) Biological signals as handicaps. J Theor Biol 144:517–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacker PMS (2007) Human nature: the categorial framework. Basil Blackwell, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacker PMS (2019) Wittgenstein meaning and mind, revised 2nd edn [first edn 1990]. Wiley, Chichester

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacker PMS (2021) The moral powers: a study of human nature. Wiley-Blackwell, Chichester

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haig D (1992) Genomic imprinting and the theory of parent-offspring conflict. Semin Dev Biol 3:153–160

    Google Scholar 

  • Haig D (1993) Genetic conflicts in human pregnancy. Q R Biol 68:495–532

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haig D (1996) Placental hormones, genomic imprinting, and maternal–fetal communication. J Evol Biol 9:357–380

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haig D (2015) Maternal–fetal conflict, genomic imprinting and mammalian vulnerabilities to cancer. Philos Trans R Soc B 370:20140178

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton WD (1964) The genetical evolution of social behaviour; I & II. J Theor Biol 7:1–52

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hrdy SB (1979) Infanticide among animals: a review, classification, and examination on the implication for the reproductive strategies of females. Ethol Sociobiol 1:13–40

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hrdy SB (1999) Mother nature: natural selection & the female of the species. Chatto & Windus, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Keegan G, Patten MM (2022) Selfish evolution of placental hormones. Evol Med Public Health 10:391–397

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kenny A (1988) Cosmological explanation and understanding. In: Herzberg L, Pietarinen J (eds) Perspectives on human conduct. Leiden, Brill, pp 72–87

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny A (1989) The metaphysics of mind. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny A (2006) A new history of Western philosophy: the rise of modern philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kozlowski J, Stearns SC (1989) Hypotheses for the production of excess zygotes: models of bet-hedging and selective abortion. Evolution 43:1369–1377

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malcolm N (1977) Thought and knowledge. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Maston GA, Ruvolo M (2002) Chorionic gonadotropin has a recent origin within primates and an evolutionary history of selection. Mol Biol Evol 19:320–335

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCoy DE, Haig D (2020) Embryo selection and mate choice: can ‘honest signals’ be trusted? Trends Ecol Evol 35:308–318

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pittendrigh CS (1958) Adaptation, natural selection and behaviour. In: Roe A, Simpson GG (eds) Behavior and evolution. Yale University Press, New Haven, pp 390–416

    Google Scholar 

  • Pusey AE, Packer C (1994) Infanticide in lions: consequences and counterstrategies. In: Parmigiani IS, vom Saal F (eds) Infanticide and parental care. Harwood, Chur, pp 277–299

    Google Scholar 

  • Rundle B (1997) Mind in action. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schiefenhövel G, Schiefenhövel W (1978) Vorgänge bei der Geburt eines Mädchens und Änderung der Infantizid-Absicht. Eipo. Irian Jaya (West-Neuguinea). Homo 29:121–138

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (1983) Intentionality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smit H (1995) Zwangerschapsmisselijkheid in een evolutionair perspectief. De Psycholoog 11:449–455

    Google Scholar 

  • Smit H (2010) Darwinisme, Monisme en Ziekte. Boom, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Smit H (2014) The social evolution of human nature: from biology to language. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smit H (2016) The transition from animal to linguistic communication. Biol Theory 11:158–172

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smit H (2018) Inclusive fitness theory and the evolution of mind and language. Erkenntnis 83:287–314

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smit H, Hacker PMS (2020) Two conceptions of consciousness and why only the neo-Aristotelian one enables us to construct evolutionary explanations. Hum Soc Sci Commun 7:93. https://doi.org/10.1057/s41599-020-00591-y

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2003) Thought in a hostile world. Blackwell Publishing Ltd, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Tinbergen N (1963) On aims and methods of ethology. Z Tierpsychol 20:410–433

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trivers RL (1974) Parent-offspring conflict. Am Zool 14:249–264

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Schaik CP (2000) Vulnerability to infanticide by males: patterns among mammals. In: van Schaik CP, Janson CP (eds) Infanticide by males and its implications. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 61–71

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Vom Saal FS (1985) Time-contingent change in infanticide and parental behavior induced by ejaculation in male mice. Physiol Behav 34:7–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White AR (1964) Attention. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • White AR (1967) The philosophy of mind. Random House, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Widdig A (2007) Paternal kin discrimination: the evidence and likely mechanisms. Biol Rev Camb Philos Soc 82:319–334

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilcox AJ, Harmon Q, Doody K, Wolf DP, Adashi EY (2020) Preimplantation loss of fertilized human ova: estimating the unobservable. Hum Reprod 35:743–750

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L ([1953]2009) Philosophical investigations. Trans: Anscombe GEM, Hacker PMS, Schulte J. Revised 4th edn; eds: Hacker PMS, Schulte J. Chichester, Wiley-Blackwell

  • Zahavi A (1981) Natural selection, sexual selection and the selection of signals. In: Scudder GGE, Reveal JL (eds) Evolution today, proceedings of the second international congress of systematic and evolution biology. Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, pp 133–138

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Peter Hacker and a reviewer for comments on an earlier version of this article.

Funding

The author did not receive any funding for the submitted research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Harry Smit.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Smit, H. An Overarching Framework for Understanding and Explaining Human Nature. Biol Theory 18, 63–75 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-022-00425-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-022-00425-x

Keywords

Navigation