Skip to main content
Log in

Reply to critics of the analytic tradition in philosophy vol. 1 the founding giants

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. The Tractatus is covered in the first 4 chapters.

  2. ATP pp. 93–94.

  3. Pp. 86–96 of ATP. Beaney asserts that he disagrees with my presentation here, but he doesn’t say why.

  4. Kneale and Kneale (1962) are cited, with Beaney, as providing “informative discussions of the relationship between Frege’s system to syllogistic logic, as well as to the logical contributions of Leibniz, Boole, and De Morgan.” p. 20. Hodes (1990) and Rayo (2002) are cited in chapter 7.

  5. ATP p. 10.

  6. ATP p. 61.

  7. ATP pp. 62–64.

  8. On page 63 I take ‘\(\exists {\text{y x}}\;{ = }\;{\text{y}}\)’ to be what should, from Frege’s point of view, be an acceptable existence predicate. Unfortunately, given (2), it isn’t.

  9. See p. 120 of ATP, where a worry about this idea is also mentioned.

  10. See Halvorson (2012) plus Thomas William Barrett and Hans Halvorson (forthcoming a, b, c).

  11. ATP pp. 252–257.

  12. Page 35, Preface to the first edition, reproduced in the second edition Moore (1903).

  13. Ibid., pp. 56–57.

  14. Ibid., Sections 16 and 17, pp. 73–78.

  15. See my “Is there a science of morality?”, unpublished ms.

  16. Russell (1919, pp. 11–12).

  17. See pp. 492–493 of ATP.

  18. Ibid., pp. 488–491.

  19. Ibid., p. 514.

  20. See chapter 7 of ATP.

  21. Ibid. p. 515.

  22. Ibid., pp. 515–520, 526.

  23. Ibid., p. 519.

  24. Ibid., pp. 516–519.

  25. Klement (2004, pp. 28–29). This is quoted on pp. 519–520 of ATP. See also Klement (2010).

  26. Ibid., pp. 520–531.

  27. ATP p. 521. A footnote to the passage notes (1) that the problem can be mitigated by letting formulas be infinitely long and (2) that Hodes (2012) develops that idea, showing it to be needed by a substitutional interpretation of higher-order quantifiers in Principia Mathematica, leading to a ramified theory of types. As Hodes notes, this approach renders Russell’s logical language incapable of being understood by agents with finite cognitive powers.

  28. Ibid., p. 523.

  29. Ibid., 531.

  30. Abstract presented on October 6, 2012 at the USC Conference on Logic and Philosophy of Science.

References

  • Barrett, T. W., & Halvorson, H. (forthcoming a). Glymour and Quine on theoretical equivalence. Philosophy of Science.

  • Barrett, T. W. (forthcoming b). Morita equivalence. Philosophy of Science.

  • Barrett, T. W. (forthcoming c). Quine’s conjecture. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

  • Beaney, M. (1996). Making sense. London: Duckworth.

  • Burgess, J. P. (2005). Fixing frege. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (1982). Frege. Brighton: Harvester Press.

  • Dejnozka, J. (1981). Frege on Identity. International Studies in Philosophy, 13, 31–41.

  • Dejnozka, J. (1996). The Ontology of the Analytic Tradition in Philosophy and Its Origins: Realism and Identity in Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein, and Quine. Lanham MD: Littlefield Adams.

  • Frege, G. (1879). Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens, Halle: L. Nebert; Preface and most of Part I trans. M. Beaney in Frege 1997, 47–78.

  • Frege, G. (1884a). Dialogue with Pünjer on Existence, trans. in Frege 1979, 53–67.

  • Frege, G. (1884b). Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik, Breslau: W. Koebner; trans. J. L. Austin, The foundations of arithmetic, Oxford: Blackwell, 1950.

  • Frege, G. (1914). Logic in mathematics, trans. in Frege 1979, pp. 203–50.

  • Frege, G. (1919). Notes for ludwig darmstaedter, trans. in Frege 1979, pp. 253–257.

  • Frege, G. (1979). Posthumous writings, trans. P. Long and R. White, Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Halvorson, H. (2012). What Scientific Theories Could Not Be. Philosophy of Science, 79, 183–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodes, H. (1990). Where do natural numbers come from? Synthese, 84, 347–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodes, H. (2012). Why Ramify, Unpublished manuscript.

  • Kaplan, D. (1968–1969). Quantifying-in, Synthese 19:178–214.

  • Kaplan, D. (1978). Dthat, in Peter Cole, ed., Syntax and semantics, vol. 9: Pragmatics, New York: Academic Press, 221–243.

  • Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klement, K. (2004). Putting form before function: logical grammar in Frege, Russell, and Wittgenstein. Philosophers Imprint www.philosophersimprint.org/004002/ 4, 2: August 2.

  • Klement, K. (2010). The Functions Of Russell’s No Class Theory. Review of Symbolic Logic, 3, 633–664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kneale, W., & Kneale, M. (1962). The development of logic. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (2008). Frege's theory of sense and reference. Theoria, 74, 181–218.

  • Landini, G. (1998). Russell’s hidden substitutional theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1912). Ethics. London, Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (1977). Frege on demonstratives. Philosophical Review, 86, 474–497.

  • Perry, J. (1979). The essential indexical. Nous, 13, 3–21.

  • Ramsey, F. P. (1925). The foundations of mathematics. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 25, 338–384.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rayo, A. (2002). Frege’s unofficial arithmetic. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 67, 1623–1638.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1903). Principles of mathematics. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1904). Review of Principia Ethica”, Independent Review 2: 328–33; reprinted as “The Meaning of Good. In A. Urquhart & A. C. Lewis (Eds.), The collected papers of Bertrand Russell (Vol. 4). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1905). On denoting. Mind, 14(1905), 479–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1919). Introduction to mathematical philosophy. London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B., & Whitehead, A. N. (1910). Principia mathematica (Vol. 1). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (2006). Response to Perry, in content and modality. In Alex Byrne & Judith Thomson (Eds.), Content and modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (2008). Our knowledge of the internal world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. Is there a science of morality? unpublished manuscript. http://dornsife.usc.edu/scottsoames

  • Thau, M., & Caplan, B. (2000). What's puzzling Gottlob Frege? Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 31, 159–200.

  • Yourgrau, P. (1982). Frege, Perry, and demonstratives. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 12, 725–752.

  • Yourgrau, P. (1986–87). The path back to Frege. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 87, 169–210.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Scott Soames.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Soames, S. Reply to critics of the analytic tradition in philosophy vol. 1 the founding giants . Philos Stud 172, 1681–1696 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0486-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0486-1

Keywords

Navigation