Skip to content
BY 4.0 license Open Access Published online by De Gruyter January 11, 2024

Why Evolutionary Psychology Is Not Feminist: Assessing the Core Values and Commitments of the Evolutionary Study of Gender Differences

  • Cristina Somcutean EMAIL logo

Abstract

Evolutionary psychology (EP) theorizes that contemporary women and men differ psychologically, particularly in mating and sexuality. It is further argued that EP research on gender-specific psychological differences is compatible with feminist perspectives. This paper analyzes if integrating EP scholarship on gender differences into feminist scholarship is possible by investigating EP’s core scientific commitments. I will argue that EP’s theories, hypotheses, and empirical findings that pertain to the study of gender do not align with its core values based on Longino’s feminist theoretical virtues as outlined in the 1996 article “Cognitive and Non-Cognitive Values in Science: Rethinking the Dichotomy.” I employ feminist theoretical virtues as tools for revealing how certain theories, models, and hypotheses rely upon, promote contentious norms, and suppress gender. I will defend the thesis that EP theories, hypotheses, and empirical findings are often empirically inadequate, androcentric, and ontologically too homogeneous. Further, EP employs single-factor control models, has no straightforward practical application, and might even be politically dangerous. These characteristics challenge a successful integration of EP into feminism.

1 Introduction

Evolutionary psychology (EP) proposes itself to be a biologically informed approach to studying human behavior (Downes 2021). A more specific version of this research program emerged around the 1990s, sometimes called narrow evolutionary psychology (Meynell 2020), which, like its mother discipline of sociobiology, suggests reducing all sociocultural features to biological features. EP of this specific form has been subject to various critiques, such as from philosophy of science, evolutionary biology, and anthropology, as well as from feminist scholars (see Downes 2021 for an overview). However, evolutionary psychologists (EPs) have maintained for decades that their scholarship, particularly their research on gender-specific psychological differences, is compatible with feminist perspectives. There have been several attempts at integration, including a book published in 1996 titled “Sex, Power, Conflict: Evolutionary and Feminist Perspectives,” edited by David Buss and Neil Malamuth with contributions by several EPs and feminist scholars. Nevertheless, as recently as 2020, feminist philosophers of science continue critiquing EP (see, for instance, Meynell 2020), and a proper integration seems far away.

In this paper, I will argue that EP’s theories, hypotheses, and empirical findings that pertain to the study of gender cannot be integrated into feminist scholarship because they do not align with the core values of feminist scientific thought. To argue for this thesis, I will use Longino’s feminist theoretical virtues as presented in her 1996 paper “Cognitive and Non-Cognitive Values in Science: Rethinking the Dichotomy” as dimensions for categorizing, assessing, and supplementing feminist critiques of EP’s perspective on gender. This paper is not meant to be an exhaustive summary of all EP theories in the outlined field of study or all feminist criticism of EP. Instead, it is aimed at presenting and evaluating some of the general complaints about EP with the addition of more targeted criticism of some specific EP theories, hypotheses, and empirical studies. For the most part, discussions of EP that primarily pertain to the philosophy of mind and cognitive science, which do not have a clear link to sex and gender, will be omitted.

With the study of gender, I refer to any research that concerns (postulated) psychological or behavioral differences between men and women, including, but not limited to, sexuality, mating, child-rearing, power relations, and violence. I will discuss selected examples to evaluate core methodological and ontological commitments and thus aid in making more generalized judgments about EP. This is possible since most EP theories of gender-specific psychological differences are based on a set of foundations, which will be introduced in the next section. Throughout this paper, I will use the terms ‘man’ and ‘woman’ when referring to the roles and behaviors that different people ought to occupy and or are said to possess because of the sex they were assigned at birth. The terms “female” and “male” will be used to indicate the roles of women and men in biological reproduction, respectively, that EP typically assumes.[1]

The paper will proceed as follows. Section 2 introduces EP’s contribution to the study of gender and lays out its core ideas and important theories and hypotheses as a primer for the following sections. Section 3 explains Longino’s (1996) feminist theoretical virtues and provides some context and motivation for using them as an evaluative framework for EP. In Section 4, I break down my analysis using each of Longino’s feminist virtues. I will discuss EP more generally as well as influential examples of the research program’s methodology, theories, hypotheses, and empirical findings through the lens of each feminist theoretical virtue. Here, I will draw on and evaluate feminist critiques of EP and other relevant literature. Lastly, Section 5 concludes.

2 Evolutionary Psychology and the Study of Gender

The central idea of EP is that most human behavior is explainable through specific psychological mechanisms, which are products of natural selection. These psychological mechanisms are posited to have been helpful to our ancestors but are not necessarily thought to be currently adaptive. It is further posited that these mechanisms are shared by all humans universally (Downes 2021). They are hypothesized to have evolved throughout the Pleistocene and to have become permanent about 12,000 years ago (Meynell 2020, 309), although not all authors explicitly state this.

When it comes to the study of gender, Buss and Schmitt offer the following perspective in their article “Evolutionary Psychology and Feminism”:

“Evolutionary psychology provides a meta-theory for predicting when and where to expect gender differences and when and where to expect gender similarities (Buss 1995) [citation in the original]. Women and men are expected to differ in domains in which they have faced recurrently different adaptive problems over human evolutionary history” (2011, 769).

These adaptive problems purportedly emerged because of anisogamy: An asymmetry between men and women in minimum parental investment is said to have arisen due to female and male gametes having different sizes. Females have to carry and breastfeed a child, whereas males are only involved in conception. Thus, females have to invest more in their offspring than males (Liesen 2007, 53f). Ancestral women purportedly faced the problems of “identifying men who are able” and “willing to invest” (Buss 1995, 165), which arose due to pregnancy and lactation, during which a female is thought to have required help with acquiring resources for survival. This is said to have led to an optimal female reproductive strategy that entails being selective (Liesen 2007, 54) and choosing a reliable, resourceful, and older mate (55).

Conversely, ancestral men faced the problems of “paternity uncertainty,” “identifying reproductively valuable women,” and “gaining sexual access to women” (Buss 1995: 165). Uncertainty about paternity is theorized to have led to the evolution of jealousy, in particular as a response to the sexual infidelity of a female mate since potentially investing in offspring that is not his own would decrease a male’s reproductive success. Attempting to control his female mate would thus be advantageous (Liesen 2007, 54). Ancestral men’s adaptive problems are also said to have emerged because ovulation and fertilization are processes within the female body about which males do not have complete information (Buss 1995, 165). Because of this information asymmetry, in theory, men have evolved a desire for ‘healthy-looking,’ conventionally attractive young women over time (Liesen 2007, 55). These traits are specifically considered markers of fertility. Anisogamy is also argued to have led to an optimal male reproductive strategy that maximizes the number of females with whom he mates (Buss 1995, 165).

To summarize: Across the board, EP theorizes that contemporary women and men differ psychologically, particularly in mating and sexuality. This is because ancestral women and men had different adaptive problems to solve based on their respective reproductive roles. The psychological mechanisms that they developed to solve those problems were inherited by humans in the present. In particular, men are believed to prefer relatively young and attractive women as mates as well as be competitive and prone to jealousy and coercive behavior towards them, and women are taken to prefer resourceful men and to be coy and nurturing. Note that none of the typical EP explanations of these behaviors take societal, cultural, or historical factors into account.

3 Longino’s Feminist Theoretical Virtues as an Evaluative Framework

According to Longino (1996), scientific theories, models, and hypotheses (from here on interchangeably referred to as ‘scientific output’) can often depart in important ways from each other in terms of content. However, because evidence underdetermines theory, different theories might be constructed on the same data. It might also be that a mere correlation between two variables in the data is hypothesized to contain a causal mechanism from one variable to the other. Thus, additional judgment is required to assess which scientific output to accept or reject (39). Feminist theoretical virtues can be understood as a set of desiderata for science. They originate from the critiques of scientific practice put forward by feminist philosophers of science and thus reflect some common values in feminist scholarship. Longino (1996) conceptualizes them as tools that can be used to guide the formulation, acceptance, and rejection of scientific theories, models, and hypotheses. She posits six feminist theoretical virtues: empirical adequacy, novelty, ontological heterogeneity, mutuality of interaction, applicability to current human needs, and diffusion of power (the latter two can be summarized under the term ‘feminist pragmatic virtues’). For the remainder of this paper, it is helpful to reformulate the purpose of feminist theoretical virtues as providing tools for revealing how certain theories, models, and hypotheses rely upon and promote contentious norms as well as suppress female and non-binary perspectives. This is in line with Fehr (2012), who states that “[f]eminist critiques are concerned with the social and political implications of research that stays consistent with and reinforces dangerous gender stereotypes” (55).

EP claims that it is not necessarily to be understood as contrasting the feminist perspective but that its scientific output can instead be integrated into the larger body of feminist scholarship (Buss and Schmitt 2011). Yet, EP has been criticized by feminist writers. Since feminist theoretical values generally reflect the feminist perspective on science, feminist theoretical virtues can be used as a framework for understanding if EPs’ compatibility claims are rooted in a deeper, genuine engagement with the values of the feminist movement, particularly as it pertains to science. One worry, especially from the perspective of EP, might be that feminist theoretical values are not an adequate evaluatory tool because they are politically motivated (see, for instance, Buss and Malamuth 1996). In response, one might refer to Fehr (2012), who clarifies that “feminist philosophers and science studies scholars (…) may be motivated by (…) political worries, [but] their assessment of EP research on gender involves critiques of its theoretical foundations, methodologies, and empirical support” (57, emphasis in original). Further, as will become more apparent as this paper progresses, EP reflects explicit or implicit political judgments as well. The worry, therefore, does not seem to be about the mere influence of political values but about which political values are acceptable and which are not – even if only implicitly endorsed. It would, therefore, be paradoxical to discount an evaluatory tool due to its potential value-ladenness.

4 The EP Perspective on Gender: A Feminist Philosophy of Science Evaluation

In the following section, I will present a critical analysis of EP’s discussion of sex and gender using Longino’s (1996) feminist theoretical virtues, one feminist virtue at a time.

4.1 Empirical Adequacy

Scientific output is considered virtuous if it is empirically adequate, i.e., if it is in accordance with the greater body of observational and experimental data. This virtue reflects work in the feminist philosophy of science that has previously shown that research based on linking differences between men and women to a set of biological causes does not fulfill minimal standards of empirical adequacy, either due to faulty research design or improper statistical methodology (Longino 1996, 45). EP’s scientific output about gender is not in accordance with other findings relevant to the study of gender, and the methodology employed to test hypotheses about the different psychologies of men and women is considered flawed. First, the conception of sex dimorphism that underlies EP research has been deemed empirically inaccurate by many. At the core, EP is committed to a particular interpretation of sex dimorphism: Humans are said to have evolved a universal mind, with the only source of variation being biological sex (see Section 2). EP, therefore, seems to assume two dimorphic sets of modules in the absolute sense. However, according to Blackless et al. (2000, 162), sex dimorphism can come in degrees: Absolute sex dimorphism means that the two forms of one species do not overlap, while moderate sex dimorphism is characteristic of species in which differences between the two forms only occur on average. The authors demonstrate that humans are moderately dimorphic, with an overlap in the size or composition of reproductive glands, genital morphology, chromosomes, and hormonal physiology close to two percent on the bimodal continuum of biological sex (i.e., intersex people). EP disregards this empirical finding altogether.[2] Some EPs might argue that moderate sex dimorphism would also be sufficient to retain their theoretical core, i.e., that average differences in physiology can be causally linked to universal gender differences in behavior. However, as will become clearer in my next point, the claim that absolute sex dimorphism is a causal factor in universal gender differences is empirically inadequate, making the argument that a weaker form of dimorphism can have the same causal effect on psychological differences even less plausible.

From an empirical adequacy standpoint, it is not only the basis for gender differences in EP that has been criticized, but also a number of the assumptions underlying theories and hypotheses about adaptive problems and reproductive strategies. For instance, Parameswaran (2014) explores evidence from historical records on several communities pre and post-European colonization. She demonstrates that EP falsely assumes fairly uniform practices of human mate selection and child-rearing across the world to be evidence of adaptive behavior. The author argues that this uniformity, which EPs take to bolster their claims about a universal human nature, is the result of European, Judeo-Christian values imposed on or adopted by colonized populations. Colonized areas of the world initially displayed great diversity in mating practices, family arrangements, gender roles, and child-rearing practices. Parameswaran (2014) criticizes that this counterevidence is either downplayed by EP or not considered altogether. How EP downplays counterevidence is highlighted in more detail by Nash (2014), who discusses the example of self-reporting data to study EP hypotheses about jealousy and promiscuity in men and choosiness in women. There are many possible factors influencing this self-reported data, such as societal gender roles and gendered expectations. However, data in accordance with EP hypotheses is taken at face value and believed to indicate ultimate causes when it is used to bolster EP hypotheses but only taken to reveal proximate causes when the results do not align with EP theories (321f).

Additionally, Fausto-Sterling (1997) criticizes that EP theories and hypotheses tend to be too vague. In particular, she is referring to the theory that ancestral women faced the adaptive problem of acquiring resources to survive pregnancy and lactation in Buss (1995) and the author’s claim that “all people are descendants of a long and unbroken line of women who successively solved this adaptive challenge” (Buss 1995, 164). It lacks specifics, Fausto-Sterling contends, such as when exactly the described reproductive behaviors are imagined to have started to appear, at what point in time the relevant traits are postulated to have become a fixed part of human genealogy,[3] in which types of environments this development might have taken place, and if there were any genetic bottlenecks[4] during evolution (1997, 241f). Moreover, she suggests that EPs should consider relevant information during theory building, such as data on the culture of prehistoric humans and protohominids, the expansion of human populations to different continents, and the literature that uses molecular evidence to track human evolution.

Not only are EP theories and hypotheses considered to be built too broadly, but they are also considered poorly tested. A critical example of how EP’s scientific output is typically tested is a large-scale international survey conducted by Buss (1994) intended to analyze EP hypotheses about women’s mate preferences. The idea is that successfully solving adaptive problems gave rise to women desiring specific traits in potential male mates. Buss (1994) hypothesizes that this is the cause of women’s behavior in mating today and accepts his hypothesis because, in the conducted surveys, women tended to favor characteristics such as good financial prospects, high social status, older age, ambition, emotional stability, intelligence, similarity in character, tallness, good health, and expressing love in a partner. Fausto-Sterling (1997) argues that this is methodologically unsound because the study uses data about contemporary humans to explain past events, but current behavior does not necessarily illuminate anything about past behavior (Fausto-Sterling 1997, 244). This is corroborated by the idea of exaptation,[5] which refers to the possibility that a trait evolves for one function but might be adapted for another, or the idea that there exist traits without any function (Meynell 2020, 307). This makes it even harder to argue that current traits can be causally traced to the behavior of our ancestors. Other methods for hypothesis testing include experimental methods as found in psychology, such as Singh’s (1993) study on male mate preferences, which was conducted by asking participants to rank pictures of women with different waist-hip ratios. Downes (2021) points out that results from such experiments cannot be taken as causal evidence that mate preferences are the result of an evolutionary mechanism. I additionally argue that testing evolutionary hypotheses using recent survey data or psychological experiments is methodologically flawed because even if the postulated psychological mechanisms exist in humans, it would be very difficult to isolate their impact on human behavior from being driven by unconscious heteropatriarchal gender roles. Thus, as it stands, EP does not fulfill the virtue of empirical adequacy. One should, therefore, be wary of any scientific output that aims to explain gender-based differences with (purported) biological differences.

4.2 Novelty

Scientific pursuit or output is considered novel if it departs in significant ways from currently accepted theories, models, and hypotheses, with the goal of either supplementing or completely replacing them. The novelty criterion is motivated by skepticism about mainstream, androcentric frameworks that potentially fail to account for current problems (Longino 1996: 46). Recently, Buss (2020) claimed that EP “is a scientific revolution, providing a fundamental paradigm shift” (316), indicating that EP is not, prima facie, motivated by conservatism. In light of this, assessing if EP research fulfills the novelty criterion is particularly interesting. In fact, EP has been criticized by feminists precisely because it does not offer novel explanations and does not concern itself with novel phenomena.

In EP, any postulated psychological differences between men and women are followed by claims about equality between the genders, such as equality of intelligence, indicating more progressive views at the surface. This stands in contrast to traditional theories of male superiority and female inferiority. However, Meynell (2012) criticizes such ‘different but equal’ explanations of men and women. She argues that “we are encouraged to think that this “new” account of dimorphic human nature is not the pernicious sex essentialism of the past” (2). ‘Essentialist’ is a term used to characterize research that relies on the idea that “certain phenomena are natural, inevitable, universal, and biologically determined” (DeLamater and Hyde 1998: 10). Meynell (2012) seems to be relating to this type of research: After closer inspection of EP theories, one finds explanations of gender psychology as biologically determined, a strategy considered one of the most conservative attempts at explaining gender. So, while claims about gender equality seem compatible with feminist thought at first glance, the method underlying the study of psychological sex differences is not novel.

Moreover, EP aims to explain phenomena that have been studied previously. Lloyd and Archer (1981) explain that psychological sex differences became an exciting field of study in the 1960s, way before EP emerged. Social psychologists started to pay attention to the subject by the 1970s and explained differences between men and women not based on biology but on social processes (287). Moreover, traditionally feminist or social scientific issues, such as violence against women, have also been tackled before EP emerged (Kelly 2014). In conclusion, EP does not fulfill the novelty criterion.

4.3 Ontological Heterogeneity

An ontologically heterogeneous theory grants equality to different kinds of entities, as opposed to ontologically homogeneous theories, which tend to erase individual differences by treating them as (inferior) variations of a particular standard entity. A well-known example of an ontologically heterogeneous scientific method is the explicit preservation of differences in the study of primates as conducted by Altmann (Longino 1996, 46f). Does EP’s scientific output grant parity to different sorts of entities without positing a standard? The sex and gender binaries present in all EP theories of gender come directly to mind. EP theories of mating and sexuality that start with anisogamy as the root of psychological differences between men and women tend to posit a dimorphic distribution of traits in absolute terms, both biologically as well as socially. Any other type of human that does not fit neatly into these binaries is erased from their ontology. Indeed, Meynell (2012, 2) criticizes that EP ignores the differences within the broad groups of men and women, respectively, and instead posits standard types, which contrasts with focusing on particularity and individuality. In Meynell’s (2012) words, EP relies on “the idea that women simpliciter are not merely of a particular type but are innately, naturally, or biologically so” (2f). A similar claim might be made about men.

So far, the argument has been about differences between men and women, respectively, but one might take it further. Relying on the idea that females and males are the standard types means being negligent towards variations of those types as previously described. Even more, it means completely erasing humans who are biologically neither strictly female nor male. EP is silent about the psychological mechanisms of intersex people because, in their theories, intersex people practically do not exist. EPs might argue that intersex people are ‘negligible’ because they are an inferior variation of a typical male or female. However, it is exactly this line of thinking that goes against ontological heterogeneity as a virtue: Difference should not be seen as something negligible or inferior, but should be treated equally to what are often considered ‘standard’ types or entities.

Another standard in EP is evidently heterosexuality. Theories about mating preferences rely on the idea that human sexuality is, for the vast majority and at least primarily, comprised of attraction to the opposite sex. The ontological commitment to heterosexuality as a standard seeps into theories about the psychology of homosexual individuals, too. For instance, EP hypothesizes that butch lesbians have similar mate preferences to heterosexual men and femme lesbians are similar to heterosexual women (Smith, Konik, and Tuve 2011: 658). This highlights the idea that homosexuality is an inferior variation of heterosexuality in EP since at the core of any relationship, EP posits typically male and female roles. We see this even more explicitly in how EP theorizes about homosexuality as “an extreme of an adaptive trait of bisexuality” (Bártová and Valentová 2012: 61) potentially adaptive for ensuring the survival of offspring. This line of reasoning shows how non-heterosexuality is conceptualized as something that bolsters scripts of heterosexual pairing and is thus treated as an inferior variation. All in all, EP posits a homogeneous ontology, and individual variation and particularity are challenging to find in EP.

4.4 Mutuality of Interaction

Mutuality of interaction can be understood as a call for a science of complex interaction: It requires that scientific output treats relationships between entities and processes as mutual rather than unidirectional and as positing multiple rather than single factor models. Because not one factor controls an outcome, mutuality of interaction reflects the rejection of dominant-subordinate relationships in scientific explanations (Longino 1996, 47). One example of how complex interaction manifests in science is Fausto-Sterling’s (2021) framework for conceptualizing gender/sex development in infants as a dynamic process consisting of phases with more or less stability in identity. Rather than positing one defining factor, the theory highlights the interaction of different factors such as lived body experience, mental life, and the environment.

Does EP posit models and theories of complex interaction? In relation to this, it is worth discussing an article by Kenrick, Trost, and Sheets (1996) on the phenomenon of so-called ‘trophy wives.’ When older, wealthy, and powerful men marry young and conventionally attractive women after divorcing their same-aged spouses, the new wife is typically called a ‘trophy wife’ (31). The authors criticize that “sociocultural views [of trophy wives] are inadvertently sexist (…) [and] imply that females are helpless pawns and males are omnipotent despots in relationships” (29f). Instead, an evolutionary perspective is deemed more suitable. More specifically, the authors claim that it is helpful to relate the phenomenon of trophy wives to sexual selection since it “assumes female choice as its most powerful driving force” (30). Regardless if their accusations against sociocultural analyses of the discussed issues are warranted, it is worth evaluating if the evolutionary perspective can offer a theory of mate choice based on complex interaction. The authors explain that female choice is the more important driver of sexual selection than male choice. The idea that female choice primarily drives sexual selection goes all the way back to Darwin’s theory of mate choice selection (Buss 1994). In the 1970s, it was argued following up on that theory that females, because of their higher minimum parental investment, are “selected to be more discriminating in choosing a mate” (240), leading to competition among males for access to females. Thus, based on this theory, multiple males might compete for sexual access to one female, but the female makes the ultimate choice (41f). As an outcome of this process, women tend to desire older, more powerful men as mates, and men prefer younger, conventionally attractive women (44f). The idea is that from an evolutionary perspective, it is advantageous for young women to pursue older, wealthy men and that they are by no means ‘helpless pawns’.

Indeed, it seems that in the theorized ancestral environment posited in EP theories, women and men are both given equal amounts of agency: Males can choose and compete for a female, and a female can accept or reject a willing male so that both females and males are assigned goals of their own. In this context, it is worth discussing Longino’s (1996) explanation of single factor models in more detail:

“(…) simple models of single factor control make one party (the dependent as distinct from the independent variable) in interaction a passive object rather than an agent. This has been the fate of female gametes in accounts of fertilization and of female organisms in accounts of social structure. Asymmetry of agency in the physiological context is used to naturalize asymmetry in the social. These naturalizing arguments are explicit in sociobiological stories attributing the presumed docility of females and activity of males to anisogamy (…)” (47, own emphasis).

Notice that even though females and males are assigned their own goals, and even though female choice is technically thought to be the primary driver in mate choice, the theory that even a seemingly feminist contribution such as Kenrick, Trost, and Sheets (1996) relies on is one that presupposes a biological asymmetry between males and females, and this asymmetry is, as Longino explains, used to argue that social behaviors are in fact natural. The agency of the respective gender is limited by its respective (imagined) reproductive role. Further, it seems that Kenrick, Trost, and Sheets (1996) attempted what Meynell (2012) refers to as a ‘different but equal’ explanation of men and women, as discussed in the subsection on novelty. At the end of the day, docile females and active males are absolutely a product of EP theories, fitting relatively neatly into the described criticism of single factor control models. Thus, EP’s scientific output does not display mutuality of interaction all the way down.

4.5 Applicability to Current Human Needs

Applicability to current human needs means that scientific output ought to be assessed based on the effects of its adoption, and research programs that can generate applicable knowledge to improve economic and social outcomes are preferred (48f). EPs might argue that this virtue is inadequate for evaluating EP’s scientific output since EPs are motivated by value-free scientific exploration (Fehr 2012, 58). In contrast to the virtues discussed above, which concern empirics, theory, and methodology, applicability to current human needs might be seen as more directly political, which might be considered problematic. However, it is widely accepted that science is not and cannot be value-free (Douglas 2009; Dupré 2007; Kitcher 2011; Putnam 2002; Rudner 1953). As outlined in the last several sections, EP can by no means be understood as a value-free, ‘purely scientific’ endeavor. EP might not explicitly claim to follow any political goals but displays a commitment to a particular worldview as a research program. This is in line with Nelson’s (2017, 259) analysis of EP as containing both empirical and normative claims. Thus, it is vital to evaluate its political impact.

So, can insights from EP be applied to improve the material conditions of humans in a way that benefits as many as possible? Criticisms entail that EP research based on absolute sexual dimorphism and biological essentialism can be politically dangerous by undoing feminist work to improve the material conditions of humans. Any effort toward the emancipation of women and queer people from gender roles would be thwarted by theories that purport to naturalize such roles. This, in essence, is Meynell’s (2020, 324) standpoint on EP’s gender essentialism and its assumptions about the nature of men and women. Moreover, the public adoption of EP findings has been argued to be a problem. Jackson and Rees (2007) argue that the mainstream dissemination of evolutionary psychology accounts poses a problem to the adoption of well-founded sociological accounts of societal issues, especially because EP can masquerade as more ‘objective.’ Moreover, according to Ging (2017), in the manosphere, a conglomeration of anti-feminist online interest groups claiming that men need to be liberated from ‘feminist delusion,’ EP findings have been used to give rise to a “uniquely misogynist, heterosexist, and racist lexicon” (649).

So far, the feminist literature on EP speaks to the issue of practical application only indirectly: Instead of simply not being able to generate applicable knowledge, EP tends to produce knowledge that can be harmful when adopted by science and popular culture. In addition, it is worthwhile to evaluate what EPs themselves suggest about applying their scientific output for practical purposes. As a last attempt to investigate EP theories’ potential for practical application, one might analyze theories about the origins of men’s coercive behavior, such as Thornhill and Palmer’s (2001) evolutionary theory of rape. The authors claim that rape is not morally justified and is currently ‘maladaptive.’ They argue that teaching young men about the causes of such predispositions might be helpful in rape prevention (Thornhill and Palmer 2001 in Nelson 2017, 262). This might indeed be a practical application of EP scholarship, but preventative measures against male violence based on EP theories might not have the desired effect. According to Nelson (2017), the way in which Thornhill and Palmer phrase that male coercive behavior used to be adaptive but is now considered ‘maladaptive’ does not negate that such behavior would reduce reproductive fitness. Instead, the way they employ the term ‘maladaptive’ seems to suggest that the behavior in question is ethically concerning because it is harmful to women in the present and thus rather signifies ‘irrational’ or ‘unwanted.’ However, the same ethical concern is not extended to ancestral women since the same kind of behavior is not viewed as ‘maladaptive’ in that case (263f). Another point of critique not discussed by Nelson might be the following: Claiming that the predisposition to rape is something males have inherited from their ancestors might be unfair towards the men who never experienced the ‘urge to rape’ and would normally go on to never display any type of violence towards women. This is because such education would paint every man as an inherently violent creature who has to fight his ‘natural’ urges.

In conclusion, EP promotes contentious gender stereotypes instead of fighting them, the latter being the goal of the feminist movement. Thus, it is difficult to see how EP would be beneficial and thus fulfill the virtue of applicability to current human needs. Therefore, it remains that EP theories have little to no potential for practical application in the ameliorative sense, and the adoption of EP theories can even be harmful.

5 Conclusions

The more influential attempts at integrating EP and feminism have so far been entirely one-sided. EPs will readily make claims about the usefulness of their scientific output for feminist scholarship but do not seem to genuinely engage with insights from feminism (Fehr 2012, 57). However, proper integration would require mutual engagement. Recently, such engagement has been endorsed again from the feminist side, for example by Fisher and Burch (2020), who attempt to demonstrate to EPs how gender studies might be useful for their discipline. This paper aimed to evaluate if integrating EP and feminism is possible in the first place by investigating EP’s core scientific commitments. Using Longino’s feminist theoretical values allowed for such an analysis. It revealed that, for the most part, EP and feminist scholarship (in the broad sense) clash in terms of ontology, the postulated direction and types of causation, what is deemed empirically satisfactory research, and based on which kinds of goals science should be pursued. More specifically, from a feminist viewpoint, EP’s scientific output is empirically inadequate, androcentric, and ontologically too homogeneous. Further, EP employs single-factor control models, has no straightforward practical application, and might even be politically dangerous. Thus, based on the fundamental makeup of EP and feminism, successful integration is not as easy as some EPs claim.


Corresponding author: Cristina Somcutean, University of Bayreuth, Universitätsstr. 30, 95447 Bayreuth, Germany, E-mail:

References

Bártová, K., and J. Valentová. 2012. “Evolutionary Perspective of Same-Sex Sexuality: Homosexuality and Homosociality Revisited.” Anthropologie 50 (1): 61–70.Search in Google Scholar

Blackless, M., A. Charuvastra, A. Derryck, A. Fausto-Sterling, K. Lauzanne, and E. Lee. 2000. “How Sexually Dimorphic Are We? Review and Synthesis.” American Journal of Human Biology 12 (2): 151–66. https://doi.org/10.1002/(sici)1520-6300(200003/04)12:2<151::aid-ajhb1>3.0.co;2-f.10.1002/(SICI)1520-6300(200003/04)12:2<151::AID-AJHB1>3.0.CO;2-FSearch in Google Scholar

Buss, D. M. 1994. “The Strategies of Human Mating.” American Scientist 82 (3): 238–49.Search in Google Scholar

Buss, D. M. 1995. “Psychological Sex Differences: Origins Through Sexual Selection.” American Psychologist 50 (3): 164–8. https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066x.50.3.164.Search in Google Scholar

Buss, D. M. 2020. “Evolutionary Psychology Is a Scientific Revolution.” Evolutionary Behavioral Sciences 14 (4): 316–23. https://doi.org/10.1037/ebs0000210.Search in Google Scholar

Buss, D. M., and N. M. Malamuth, eds. 1996. Sex, Power, Conflict: Evolutionary and Feminist Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780195095814.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Buss, D. M., and D. P. Schmitt. 2011. “Evolutionary Psychology and Feminism.” Sex Roles 64 (9–10): 768–87. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11199-011-9987-3.Search in Google Scholar

DeLamater, J. D., and J. S. Hyde. 1998. “Essentialism vs. Social Constructionism in the Study of Human Sexuality.” The Journal of Sex Research 35 (1): 10–8. https://doi.org/10.1080/00224499809551913.Search in Google Scholar

Douglas, H. E. 2009. Science, Policy, and the Value-Free Ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.10.2307/j.ctt6wrc78Search in Google Scholar

Downes, S. M. 2021. “Evolutionary Psychology.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2021st ed., edited by E. N. Zalta. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/evolutionary-psychology/ (accessed September 14, 2022).Search in Google Scholar

Dupré, J. 2007. “Fact and Value.” In Value-Free Science? Ideals and Illusions, edited by H. Kincaid, J. Dupré, and A. Wylie. New York: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195308969.003.0003Search in Google Scholar

Fausto-Sterling, A. 1997. “Beyond Difference: A Biologist’s Perspective.” Journal of Social Issues 53 (2): 233–58. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-4560.1997.tb02442.x.Search in Google Scholar

Fausto-Sterling, A. 2021. “A Dynamic Systems Framework for Gender/Sex Development: From Sensory Input in Infancy to Subjective Certainty in Toddlerhood.” Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 15: 1–19, https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2021.613789.Search in Google Scholar

Fehr, C. 2012. “Feminist Engagement With Evolutionary Psychology.” Hypatia 27 (1): 50–72. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1527-2001.2011.01221.x.Search in Google Scholar

Fisher, M. L., and R. L. Burch. 2020. “Evolutionary Psychology and Gender Studies.” In The SAGE Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology: Integration of Evolutionary Psychology With Other Disciplines, edited by T. K Shackelford, 350–75. London: SAGE.10.4135/9781529739435.n18Search in Google Scholar

Ging, D. 2017. “Alphas, Betas, and Incels: Theorizing the Masculinities of the Manosphere.” Men and Masculinities 22 (4): 638–57, https://doi.org/10.1177/1097184x17706401.Search in Google Scholar

Jackson, S., and A. Rees. 2007. “The Appalling Appeal of Nature: The Popular Influence of Evolutionary Psychology as a Problem for Sociology.” Sociology 41 (5): 917–30. https://doi.org/10.1177/0038038507080445.Search in Google Scholar

Kelly, S. 2014. “Tofu Feminism: Can Feminist Theory Absorb Evolutionary Psychology?” Dialectical Anthropology 38 (3): 287–304. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10624-014-9353-2.Search in Google Scholar

Kenrick, D. T., M. R. Trost, and V. L. Sheets. 1996. “Power, Harassment, and Trophy Mates: The Feminist Advantages of an Evolutionary Perspective.” In Sex, Power, Conflict: Evolutionary and Feminist Perspectives, edited by D. M. Buss, and N. M. Malamuth, 29–53. New York: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780195095814.003.0003Search in Google Scholar

Kitcher, P. 2011. Science in a Democratic Society. Amherst: Prometheus Books.10.1163/9789401207355_003Search in Google Scholar

Liesen, L. T. 2007. “Women, Behavior, and Evolution: Understanding the Debate Between Feminist Evolutionists and Evolutionary Psychologists.” Politics and the Life Sciences 26 (1): 51–77. https://doi.org/10.2990/21_1_51.Search in Google Scholar

Lloyd, B. B., and J. Archer. 1981. “Problems and Issues in Research on Gender Differences.” Current Psychological Reviews 1 (3): 287–304. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf02684490.Search in Google Scholar

Longino, H. E. 1996. “Cognitive and Non-Cognitive Values in Science: Rethinking the Dichotomy.” In Feminism, Science, and the Philosophy of Science, edited by L. H. Nelson, and J. Nelson, 39–58. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands.10.1007/978-94-009-1742-2_3Search in Google Scholar

Meynell, L. 2012. “Evolutionary Psychology, Ethology, and Essentialism (Because What They Don’t Know Can Hurt Us).” Hypatia 27 (1): 3–27. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1527-2001.2011.01240.x.Search in Google Scholar

Meynell, L. 2020. “What’s Wrong With (Narrow) Evolutionary Psychology.” In The Routledge Handbook of Feminist Philosophy of Science, edited by S. L. Crasnow, and K. Intemann, 303–15. New York: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group.10.4324/9780429507731-29Search in Google Scholar

Nash, A. 2014. “Are Stone-Age Genes Created Out of Whole Cloth? Evaluating Claims About the Evolution of Behavior.” Dialectical Anthropology 38 (3): 305–32. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10624-014-9354-1.Search in Google Scholar

National Geographic Society. 2022. Genetic Bottleneck, 13 September. https://education.nationalgeographic.org/resource/genetic-bottleneck (accessed September 14, 2022).Search in Google Scholar

Nelson, L. H. 2017. “Evolutionary Psychology, Feminist Critiques Thereof, and the Naturalistic Fallacy.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Evolutionary Ethics, edited by M. Ruse, and R. J. Richards, 257–72. New York: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/9781316459409.019Search in Google Scholar

Parameswaran, G. 2014. “Are Evolutionary Psychology Assumptions About Sex and Mating Behaviors Valid? A Historical and Cross-Cultural Exploration.” Dialectical Anthropology 38 (3): 353–73. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10624-014-9356-z.Search in Google Scholar

Parry, W. 2013. “Exaptation: How Evolution Uses What’s Available.” Live Science, 17 September. https://www.livescience.com/39688-exaptation.html (accessed September 24, 2022).Search in Google Scholar

Putnam, H. 2002. The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy and Other Essays. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Rudner, R. 1953. “The Scientist Qua Scientist Makes Value Judgments.” Philosophy of Science 20 (1): 1–6. https://doi.org/10.1086/287231.Search in Google Scholar

Singh, D. 1993. “Adaptive Significance of Female Physical Attractiveness: Role of Waist-To-Hip Ratio.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 65 (2): 293–307. https://doi.org/10.1037//0022-3514.65.2.293.Search in Google Scholar

Smith, C. A., J. A. Konik, and M. V. Tuve. 2011. “In Search of Looks, Status, or Something Else? Partner Preferences Among Butch and Femme Lesbians and Heterosexual Men and Women.” Sex Roles 64 (9–10): 658–68. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11199-010-9861-8.Search in Google Scholar

Thornhill, R., and C. T. Palmer. 2001. A Natural History of Rape: Biological Bases of Sexual Coercion. Cambridge: MIT Press.Search in Google Scholar

Tooby, J., and L. Cosmides. 2015. “Conceptual Foundations of Evolutionary Psychology.” In The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology, edited by D. M Buss. Hoboken, New Jersey: John Wiley & Sons.10.1002/9780470939376.ch1Search in Google Scholar


Supplementary Material

This article contains supplementary material (https://doi.org/10.1515/krt-2023-0022).


Received: 2023-06-18
Accepted: 2023-12-27
Published Online: 2024-01-11

© 2024 the author(s), published by De Gruyter, Berlin/Boston

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

Downloaded on 27.4.2024 from https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/krt-2023-0022/html
Scroll to top button