Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Hate Speech and Distorted Communication: Rethinking the Limits of Incitement

  • Published:
Law and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Hate speech is commonly defined with reference to the legal category of incitement. Laws targeting incitement typically focus on how the speech is expressed rather than its actual content. This has a number of unintended consequences: first, law tends to capture overt or obvious forms of hate speech and not hate speech that takes the form of ‘reasoned’ argument, but which nevertheless, causes as much, if not more harm. Second, the focus on form rather than content leads to categorization errors. Hate speech taking the form of ‘reasoned argument’ is often legally characterized as either political or academic debate, and so is deemed both permissible and justified in societies where free speech principles exist. In this paper, I argue that it is important to identify instances of hate speech as hate speech, no matter how articulately or reasonably the speech is expressed. The danger in mischaracterizing an instance of hate speech by calling it academic or political debate is that it risks normalizing the views and sentiments that are expressed and accepting those views as an important part of our political and academic discourses. With reference to Habermas’ account of ‘distorted communication’, I propose different criteria for defining and understanding hate speech and suggest that there might be good reasons for interpreting the concept of incitement more broadly, so as to include these different kinds of it.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • A. Allen, The Politics of Our Selves: Power, Autonomy and Gender in Contemporary Critical Theory (New York: Columbia University Press, 2008).

    Google Scholar 

  • B. Applebaum, ‘Social Justice, Democratic Education and the Silencing of Words that Wound’, Journal of Moral Education 32(2) (2003): pp. 151–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • A. Altman, ‘Liberalism and Campus Hate Speech: A Philosophical Examination’, Ethics 103(2) (1993): pp. 302–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • V. Blasi, ‘The Checking Value in First Amendment Theory’, American Bar Foundation Research Journal 2(3) (1977): pp. 521–552.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Boham, ‘Distorted Communication: Formal Pragmatics as a Critical Theory’, in Lewis Edwin Hahn (ed.), Perspectives on Habermas (Chicago: Open Court Publishing, 2000).

    Google Scholar 

  • S.J. Brison, ‘The Autonomy Defense of Free Speech’, Ethics 108(2) (1998): pp. 312–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • H. Chisick, ‘The Dual Threat to Modern Citizenship: Liberal Indifference and Nonconsensual Violence’, in R. Cohen-Almagor (ed.), Liberal Democracy and the Limits of Tolerance (Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press, 2000).

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Cohen, ‘Freedom of Expression’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 22(3) (1993): pp. 207–263.

    Google Scholar 

  • D. Fraser, ‘On the Internet, Nobody Knows You’re a Nazi’: Some Comparative Legal Aspects of Holocaust Denial on the WWW’, in I. Hare and J. Weinstein (eds.), Extreme Speech and Democracy (New York: Oxford University Press, 2009).

    Google Scholar 

  • K. Gelber, Speaking Back: The Free Speech Versus Hate Speech Debate (Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • J. Habermas, 1984, A Theory of Communicative Action: Reason and the Rationalisation of Society, trans. Thomas A. McCarthy (Boston, Mass: Beacon Press, 1984).

  • J. Habermas, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, trans. William Rehg (Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1999).

  • J. Habermas, ‘Reflections on Communicative Pathology (1974)’, in On the Pragmatics of Social Interaction: Preliminary Studies in the Theory of Communicative Action, trans. Barbara Fultner (Cambridge, Mass: The MIT Press, 2001).

  • S. Hurley, ‘Imitation, Media Violence, and Freedom of Speech’, Philosophical Studies, 117(1–2) (2004): pp. 165–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • A.W. Jeremy, ‘Religious Offences’, Ecclesiastical Law Journal 7(33) (2003): pp. 127–142.

  • I. Maitra, ‘Subordinating Speech’, in Ishani Maitra and Mary Kate McGowan (eds.), Speech and Harm (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • G. Mason, ‘The Reconstruction of Hate Language’, in K. Gelber and A. Stone (eds.), Hate Speech and Freedom of Speech in Australia (Sydney: The Federation Press, 2007), pp. 34–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • M.J. Matsuda, ‘Public Response to Racist Speech: Considering the Victim’s Story’, Michigan Law Review 87(8) (1989): pp. 2320–2381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • J.S. Mill, On Liberty (London: Penguin Books, 1985).

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Moles, ‘Autonomy, Free Speech and Automatic Behaviour’, Res Publica 13(1) (2007): p. 5375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • C. McKinnon, ‘Should we Tolerate Holocaust Denial?’, Res Publica 13(1) (2007): pp. 9–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • R. Post, ‘Hate Speech’, in I. Hare and J. Weinstein (eds.), Extreme Speech and Democracy (New York: Oxford University Press, 2009).

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971).

    Google Scholar 

  • S. Sorial, Sedition and the Advocacy of Violence: Free Speech and Counter-Terrorism (London: Routledge, 2011).

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarah Sorial, ‘Free Speech, Autonomy, and the Marketplace of Ideas’, Journal of Value Inquiry 44 (2010): pp. 167–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D.A. Strauss, ‘Persuasion, Autonomy, and Freedom of Expression’, Columbia Law Review 91(2) (1991): pp. 334–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • T.A. Van Dijk, ‘Discourse and the Denial of Racism’, Discourse and Society 3(1) (1992): pp. 87–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • T.A. Van Dijk, Elite Discourse and Racism (Thousand Oaks: SAGE, 1993).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • J. Waldron, Liberal Rights: Collected Papers 1981–1991 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Waldron, The Harm in Hate Speech (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 2012).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • C. Yong, ‘Does Freedom of Speech Include Hate Speech?’, Res Publica 17(4) (2011): pp. 385–403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Cases

  • Smith v Collin, 432 U.S. 43 (1977).

  • Snyder v Phelps 562 U.S (2011).

  • Norwood v DPP [2004] EWHC 69 (Admin).

  • Hammond v DPP [2004] EWHC 69 (Admin).

  • Jones v Toben [2002] FCA 1150.

  • Sabina Citron and Canadian Human Rights Commission and Ernst Zundel and League for Human Rights of B’nai Canada, Reasons for Decision, Canadian Human Rights Tribunal, T.D. 2002.

Legislation

  • Anti-Discrimination Act 1977 (NSW).

  • Anti-Discrimination Act 1991 (Qld).

  • Racial Vilification Act 1996 (SA).

  • Racial and Religious Tolerance Act 2001 (Vic).

  • Criminal Code, R.S.C. ch. C-46, S 319 (1) (2) (1980).

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sarah Sorial.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sorial, S. Hate Speech and Distorted Communication: Rethinking the Limits of Incitement. Law and Philos 34, 299–324 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10982-014-9214-9

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10982-014-9214-9

Keywords

Navigation