Skip to main content

Sociology of Science, Rule Following and Forms of Life

  • Chapter
History of Philosophy of Science

Part of the book series: Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook [2001] ((VCIY,volume 9))

Abstract

Ludwig Wittgenstein was trained as a scientist and an engineer. He received a diploma in mechanical engineering from the Technische Hochschule in Charlottenburg, Berlin, in 1906, after which he did several years of research on aeronautics before turning to the full-time study of logic and philosophy. Hertz, Boltzmann, Mach, Weininger, and William James, all important influences on Wittgenstein, are authors whose work was both philosophical and scientific. The relationship between everyday life, science, and philosophy, is a central concern throughout the course of his writing. He regarded philosophy, properly conducted, as an autonomous activity, a matter of clarifying our understanding of language, or investigating grammar. Wittgenstein thought philosophy should state the obvious as a way of disabusing us of the desire to formulate philosophical theories of meaning, knowledge, language, or science, and was deeply opposed to the naturalist view that philosophy is a form of science. In his later work, Wittgenstein rejected systematic approaches to understanding language and knowledge. Wittgenstein’s answer to the Socratic question about the nature of knowledge is that it has no nature, no essence, and so it is a mistake to think one can give a single systematic answer:

If I was asked what knowledge is, I would list items of knowledge and add “and suchlike.” There is no common element to be found in all of them, because there isn’t one. (Wittgenstein, MS 302, “Diktat Mr Schlick” 1931–33.)

I would like to thank the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation and the Department of Philosophy at the University of Bielefeld for their generous support while I was writing this paper, and the audience at my IWK presentation for their constructive comments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Barnes, Barry, David Bloor and John Henry: (1996) Scientific Knowledge: A Sociological Analysis. Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, Barry and David Edge (eds.): (1982) Science in Context: Readings in the Sociology of Science. Open University Press, Milton Keynes, England.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S.: (1984) Spreading the word, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S.: (1984a) “The individual strikes back”, in Wright, C. (ed.): 1984, Essays on Wittgenstein’s later philosophy, Synthese 58, #3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, David: (1973) “Wittgenstein and Mannheim on the sociology of mathematics” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 4 173–191. Reprinted in Collins 1982 39–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, David: (1976/1991) Knowledge and Social Imagery, Routledge. Second revised edition, Chi-cago University Press, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, David: (1983) Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge. Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, David: (1992) “Left and Right Wittgensteinians” in Pickering 1992, 266–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, David: (1996) “The Question of Linguistic Idealism Revisited” in Sluga and Stern 1996, 354382.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, David: (1997) Wittgenstein, Rules and Institutions. Routledge, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, David: (2001) “Wittgenstein and the Priority of Practice” in Schatzki et. al. 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, Robert B.: (1994) Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cerbone, David R.: (1995) “Don’t Look But Think: Imaginary Scenarios in Wittgenstein’s Later Philosophy” Inquiry 37, 159–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, Harry: (1974) “The TEA set: tacit knowledge and scientific networks” Science Studies 4 165–186. Reprinted in Barnes and Edge 1982, 44–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, Harry: (1975) “The Seven Sexes: A Study in the Sociology of a Phenomenon, or the Replication of Experiments in Physics” Sociology 9 205–224. Reprinted in Barnes and Edge 1982, 94–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, Harry (ed.): (1982) Sociology of Scientific Knowledge: A Source Book. Bath University Press, Bath, England.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, Harry: (1983) “An empirical relativist programme in the sociology of scientific knowledge”, in Knorr-Cetina and Mulkay 1983, 85–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, Harry: (1985/1991) Changing Order: Replication and Order in Scientific Practice. Sage, London and Beverly Hills, CA. Second revised edition, University of Chicago Press, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, Harry: (2001), Harry: (2001) “What is Tacit Knowledge?” in Schatzki et. al. 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, Harry and Trevor Pinch: (1993/1999) The Golem: What Everyone Should Know About Science. Cambridge University Press, London. Second revised edition, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, Harry, and Steven Yearly: (1992) “Epistemological Chicken” in Pickering 1992, 301–326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, Harry, and Steven Yearly: (1992a) “Journey into Space” in Pickering 1992, 369–389.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coulter, Jeff: (1993) “Logic: ethnomethodology and the logic of language” in Ethnomethodology and the Human Sciences ed. Graham Button. Cambridge University Press, 20–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, Michael: (1959) “Wittgenstein’s Philosophy of Mathematics” Philosophical Review 68 324–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Michael: (1998) “On the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge and its Philosophical Agenda” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 29 239–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, Steve: (1996) “Talking Turkey About Epistemological Chicken, and the Poop on Pidgins” in Galison and Stump 1996, 170–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galison, Peter and David J. Stump (eds.): (1996) The Disunity of Science: Boundaries, Contexts, and Power. Stanford University Press, Stanford CA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Golinski, Jan: (1998) Making Natural Knowledge: Constructivism and the History of Science. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, ian: (1984) “Wittgenstein Rules,” review of Bloor (1983), Social Studies of Science 14, 469–476.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, Ian: (1999) The Social Construction of What? Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaiser, David: (1998) “A Mannheim for All Seasons: Bloor, Merton, and the Roots of Sociology of Scientific Knowledge” Science in Context 11:1, 51–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S.: (1982) Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas: (1962/1970) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. University of Chicago Press. Second revised edition, 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, Michael: (1992) “Extending Wittgenstein: The Pivotal Move from Epistemology to the Sociology of Science” in Pickering 1992, 215–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, Michael: (1992a) “From the `Will to Theory’ to the Discursive Collage: A Reply to Bloor’s `Left and Right Wittgensteinians— in Pickering 1992, 283–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, Michael: (1993) Scientific Practice and Ordinary Action: Ethnomethodology and Social Studies of Science. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John: (1993) “Meaning and Intentionality in Wittgenstein’s Later Philosophy” in Midwest Studies in Philosophy Volume XVII: The Wittgenstein Legacy. Notre Dame University Press, Notre Dame, IN, 40–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, Colin: (1984) Wittgenstein on meaning, Blackwell, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pels, Dick: (1996) “Karl Mannheim and the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge: Toward a New Agenda” Sociological Theory 14: I 30–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, Derek L.: (1977) Wittgenstein and Scientific Knowledge: A Sociological Perspective. Row-man and Littlefield, Totowa, NJ.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, Andrew (ed.): (1992) Science as Practice and Culture. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, Andrew: (1992a) “From Science as Knowledge to Science as Practice” in Pickering 1992 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Staten, H.: 1984, Wittgenstein and Derrida: philosophy, language and deconstruction, Blackwell, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, Stephen: (1994) The Social Theory of Practices: Tradition, Tacit Knowledge, and Presuppositions. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ritsert, Jürgen: (1991) “The Wittgenstein-Problem in Sociology or: The ‘Linguistic Turn’ as a Pirouette” Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and Humanities 22 7–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, Paul: (1987) Meaning and Method in the Social Sciences: A Case for Methodological Plu-ralism. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, Paul: (1996) “Will the Real Scientists Please Stand Up? Dead Ends and Live issues in the Explanation of Scientific Knowledge” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 27 43–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth, Paul: (1998) “What does the sociology of scientific knowledge explain?: or, when epistemo- logical chickens come home to roost” History of the Human Sciences 7 95–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schatzki, Theodore: (1996) Social Practices: A Witigensteinian Approach to Human Activity and the Social. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schatzki, Theodore, Karin Knorr-Cetina and Eike von Savigny (eds.): (2001) The Practice Turn in Contemporary Theory. Routledge, London and New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, Steven: (1982) “History of science and its sociological reconstructions” History of Science 20 157–211.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, Steven and Schaffer, Simon: (1985) Leviathan and the Air Pump: Hobbes, Boyle and the Experimental L. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sluga, Hans and David Stern (eds.): (1996) The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, David: (1994) “Recent work on Wittgenstein, 1980–1990” Synthese 98 415–458. Stern, David: (1995) Wittgenstein on mind and language, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, David: (1996) “The availability of Wittgenstein’s philosophy,” in Sluga and Stern 1996, 442–476.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, David: (2000) “Practices, practical holism, and background practices,” in Heidegger, Coping, and Cognitive Science: Essays in Honor of Hubert L. Dreyf rs, Volume 2 Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stem, David: (forthcoming) “The Practical Turn” in The Blackwell Guidebook to the Philosophy of the Social Sciences,ed. Stephen Turner and Paul Roth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, Peter: (1958/1990) The Idea of a Social Science and its Relation to Philosophy. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London. Second revised edition, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, Peter: (1964) “Understanding a Primitive Society” American Philosophical Quarterly 130724.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, Peter: (1987) “Language, Thought and World in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus” in Trying to Make Sense, Blackwell, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig: (1922) Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, translation on facing pages by C. K. Ogden. Routledge and Kegan Paul. Second edition, 1933.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig: (1953/1958) Philosophical Investigations, edited by G. E. M. Anscombe and R. Rhees, translation on facing pages by G. E. M. Anscombe. Blackwell, Oxford. Second edition, 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woolgar, Steve: (1981) “Interests and Explanation in the Social Study of Science” Social Studies of Science 11 365–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woolgar, Steve: (1983) “Irony in the Social Study of Science” in Knorr-Cetina and Mulkay 1983, 239–266.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woolgar, Steve: (1988) Science: The Very Idea. Routledge, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woolgar, Steve (ed.): (1988a) Knowledge and Reflexivity: New Frontiers in the Sociology of Science. Sage, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woolgar, Steve: (1992) “Some Remarks about Positionism: A Reply to Collins and Yearly” in Pickering 1992, 327–342.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2002 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Stern, D. (2002). Sociology of Science, Rule Following and Forms of Life. In: Heidelberger, M., Stadler, F. (eds) History of Philosophy of Science. Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook [2001], vol 9. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1785-4_27

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1785-4_27

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5976-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-1785-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics