Skip to main content
Log in

The Goodman Paradox: Three Different Problems and a Naturalistic Solution to Two of Them

  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is now more than 50 years that the Goodman paradox has been discussed, and many different solutions have been proposed. But so far no agreement has been reached about which is the correct solution to the paradox. In this paper, I present the naturalistic solutions to the paradox that were proposed in Quine (1969, 1974), Quine and Ullian (1970/1978), and Stemmer (1971). At the same time, I introduce a number of modifications and improvements that are needed for overcoming shortcomings of the solutions. The discussion of this improved version suggests that the Goodman paradox actually embodies three different problems; yet, one of them is not Goodman’s but Hume’s problem. The discussion also suggests that the naturalistic approach is probably the best for basing on it a theory of confirmation. Finally, I analyze one of Hume’s insights that seems to have been largely ignored. This insight shows a surprising similarity to a central feature of the naturalistic solutions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Ackerman, R.: (1969), ‘Sortal Predicates and Confirmation’, Philosophical Studies 20, 1–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baege, B.: (1933), ‘Zur Entwicklung der Verhaltensweise junger Hunde’, Zeitschrift für Hundeforschung 3, 3–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R.: (1947), ‘On the Application of Inductive Logic’, Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 8, 133–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R.: (1950), Logical Foundations of Probability,University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Catania, A. C.: (1998), Learning,Prentice Hall, Upper Saddle River.

    Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J.: (1992), Bayest or Bust? A Critical Examination of Bayesian Confirmation Theory,MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardenfors, P.: (1990), ‘Induction, Conceptual Spaces and AI’, Philosophy of Science 57, 78–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N.: (1965), Fact, Fiction, and Forecast,Bobbs-Merrill, Indianapolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N.: (1972), Problems and Projects,Bobbs-Merrill, Indianapolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G.: (1994), ‘Simplicity as a Pragmatic Criterion for Deciding What Hypotheses to Take Seriously’, in: Stalker, D. (1994). Grue!Open Court, Chicago, 153–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G.: (1965), Aspects of Scientific Explanation,Free Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S.: (2001), ‘Why There Need Not Be Any Grue Problem About Inductive Inference as Such’, Philosophy 76, 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D.: (1748/1975), An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding,Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. C.: (1983), The Logic of Decision,University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P.: (1992), ‘The Naturalists Return’, The Philosophical Review 101, 53–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Konyndyk, K. Jr.: (1980), ‘Solving Goodman’s Paradox: A Reply to Stemmer’, Philosophical Studies 37, 297–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M.: (1994), ‘Earman on the Projectibility of Grue’, in: Hull, D. Forbes, M. and Burian, R. M. (eds.), PSA 1994, vol. 1, Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, 87–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R.: (1963), Conjectures and Refutations,Harper & Row, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V.: (1960), Word and Object,Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.: (1969), ‘Natural Kinds’, in Quine, W.V. (ed.), Ontological Relativity and Other Essays,). Columbia University Press, New York, 114–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.: (1974), The Roots of Reference,Open Court, La Salle, IL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V. and Ullian, J.S.: (1970/1978), The Web of Belief,Random House, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanford, D.H.: (1994), ‘A Grue Thought in a Bleen Shade: ‘Grue’ as a Disjunctive Predicate’, in Stalker, D. (ed.), Grue!Open Court, Chicago, 173–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalker, D.: (1994), Grue!, Open Court, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stemmer, N.: (1971), ‘Three Problems in Induction’, Synthese 23, 287–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stemmer, N.: (1975), ‘The Goodman Paradox’, Zeitschrift für allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 6, 340–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stemmer, N.: (1978), ‘A Partial Solution to the Goodman Paradox’, Philosophical Studies 34, 177–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stemmer, N.: (1983), The Roots of Knowledge,Blackwell, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stemmer, N.: (1988), ‘Hume’s Two Assumptions’, Dialectica 42, 93–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stemmer, N.: (2001), ‘The Mind-Body Problem and Quine’s Repudiation Theory’, Behavior and Philosophy 29, 187–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, S.: (1987), Animal Learning: An Introduction,Routledge Kegan Paul, London.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nathan Stemmer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Stemmer, N. The Goodman Paradox: Three Different Problems and a Naturalistic Solution to Two of Them. J Gen Philos Sci 35, 351–370 (2004). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-004-4553-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-004-4553-0

Key words

Navigation