Skip to main content
Log in

Bridging the Gap: A Reply to Hutto and Satne

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Daniel D. Hutto and Glenda Satne expose, and suggest a way to resolve, what they see as an “essential tension” which has plagued what they take to be, rightly I think, the most promising approach to the nature of contentful states, that is, the neo-pragmatist approach, according to which an adequate account of content essentially appeals to the notion of a social practice. This paper is a critical assessment of their proposal. On their view, the tension stems from the fact that participation in a social practice seems to require that, in order to participate in one, an individual must have contentful states, which entails that participation in social practices cannot explain the origin of contentful states. They argue that the tension dissipates once contentless forms of intentionality come into view. I show that the tension cannot be addressed in the way in which the authors suggest, for the intermediate steps between primitive intentionality and contentful intentionality cannot in fact fully be accounted for. Nevertheless, the authors shed valuable light on the location and scope of the gap in the transition between mindlessness and contentful mindedness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For other rehearsals of the idea that a naturalistically respectable theory should provide necessary and sufficient conditions for representation, see Stich (1992) and Tye (1992).

  2. Daniel Hutto seems to distinguish between the question of the horizontal factors and the question of the vertical factors in Hutto 1999. But he conflates the problem of the vertical factors with the problem of misrepresentation or the disjunction problem (Hutto 1999, 44). The two problems are distinct, and the first one is more fundamental than the second. To repeat, the vertical problem is essentially the question of which of the indefinitely many aspects of the object are captured in representation, and it must be answered in order to understand how representations emerge. (Here I am using the notion of representation in a broad sense, without committing myself to the representational theory of mind.) The misrepresentation problem is the question of how it is possible for a representation to be false. If one is an informational semanticist, one might have good reason to think that solving one of the problems amounts to also solving the other one.

  3. That which is viewed as tension may be captured equally satisfactorily by invoking the notion of circularity: neo-pragmatists fail to give satisfactory accounts of content because their explanations are circular, insofar as they presuppose what they are meant to explain. This strand of criticism has been raised against Davidson’s account (see, for example, Yalowitz 1999). See Myers and Verheggen, forthcoming, for a detailed treatment of it.

  4. See Hutto and Myin 2013 for an elaborate account of contentless intentionality. The account is based on the claim that, “once one abandons the idea that mentality is essentially content involving there is no a priori reason to suppose that cognition is an exclusively heady affair” (2013, 12).

  5. Because primitive intentionality lacks content, attributions of primitive intentionality, unlike attributions of content, do not generate intensional contexts, that is, contexts in which the substitution of co-referential terms may result in a change in the truth value of the sentence. Such attributions are fully extensional, and there is no reason to think that primitive intentionality cannot receive complete characterizations in extensional terms.

  6. They write that, “what is missing from the story is an account of how to bridge the gap between the two [stages]. This is precisely what third basers [the neo-pragmatists] can provide” (Hutto and Satne, 24).

  7. One might object by saying that functions are not tantamount to physical particulars, and yet there does not seem to be any principled reason for which an account of their emergence cannot be had. I hope that it has become clear by now, however, that the notion of content cannot be explained in terms of the notion of function.

  8. This objection and the example that follows have been suggested by Dan Hutto.

  9. I am not suggesting that no light can be shed on the acquisition of the novel kind of mentality, for that would be to ignore the progress that, say, developmental psychology has made in recent decades. Rather, I am suggesting that the explanations supplied are bound to shed light either on one or on the other of the two sides of the unbridgeable gap, and cannot bridge that gap.

  10. Dorit Bar-On argues against continuity scepticism in her paper. Her strategy is to carve a middle ground between natural meaning and non-natural meaning. I do not have the space to discuss her proposal. I will just mention that it is not clear to me that expressive signals and behaviours, which are offered as middle ground, and constitute “natural precursors of objective thought” (2013, 324), cannot be elucidated in terms that are fully extensional (i.e., which do not generate intensional contexts). While Bar-On may be right to think that a “purely causal construal fails to do justice to the richness and complexity of these behaviours” (2013, 318), her arguments do not establish that a construal that is extensionally specified, in terms of targeted responses, is unsatisfactory, and so, to use the vocabulary introduced in this paper, they do not show that expressive signals and behaviours are not, in fact, mere instances of primitive intentionality. But if I am right, expressive behaviour cannot constitute a middle ground between primitive intentionality and full-blown intentionality. See also Bar-On and Green (2010) for a very illuminating discussion of the general project of “charting a path that could put a languageless creature on her way to language,” which is the very close vicinity of the general question addressed in this paper.

References

  • Bar-On, D. (2013). Expressive communication and continuity skepticism. Journal of Philosophy, 110(6), 293–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bar-On, D., & Green, M. (2010) Lionspeak: Communication, expression, and meaning. In J. R. O’Shea & E. Rubenstein (eds.), Self, language, and world: Problems from Kant, Sellars, and Rosenberg (89–106). Ridgeview Publishing Co.

  • Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1999). The emergence of thought. Erkenntnis, 51(1), 7–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (2001a). Subjective, intersubjective, objective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (2001b). What thought requires. In J. Branquinho (Ed.), The foundations of cognitive science. Oxford: Clarendon. Reprinted in Problems of Rationality.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (2004). Problems of rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (2003). Responses to Barry Stroud, John McDowell, and Tyler Burge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67(3), 691–699.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1984). Semantics, wisconsin style. Synthese, 59(3), 231–250. doi:10.2307/20116001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1989). Misinformation. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 19(4), 533–550.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (1990). The intentionality all-stars. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 383–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D.D. (1999). The presence of mind. John Benjamins Publishing.

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D.D., & Satne, G. The Natural Origins of Content. Forthcoming in Philosophia, (present issue).

  • Kornblith, H. (1994). Naturalism: both metaphysical and epistemological. Midwest Studies In Philosophy, 19(1), 39–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myers, R. H., & Verheggen, C. (Forthcoming). Donald Davidson’s Triangulation Argument: A Philosophical Inquiry. Routledge.

  • Shea, N. (2013). Naturalising representational content. Philosophy Compass, 8(5), 496–509. doi:10.1111/phc3.12033.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1992). What is a theory of mental representation? Mind, 101(402), 243–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (1992). Naturalism and the mental. Mind, 101(403), 421–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yalowitz, S. (1999). Davidson’s social externalism. Philosophia, 27, 99–136. doi:10.1007/BF02380998.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Olivia Sultanescu.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sultanescu, O. Bridging the Gap: A Reply to Hutto and Satne. Philosophia 43, 639–649 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-015-9625-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-015-9625-3

Keywords

Navigation