Skip to main content

Carelessness and Inattention: Mind-Wandering and the Physiology of Fantasy from Locke to Hume

  • Chapter
The Body as Object and Instrument of Knowledge

Part of the book series: Studies in History and Philosophy of Science ((AUST,volume 25))

Abstract

Associated ideas, complained Locke, follow one another “without any care or attention.” In a brilliant inversion of Locke’s nervous worries about the perils of misassociation, Hume resolved the sceptical despair brought on by philosophical reasoning only by returning to mindlessness: “carelessness and in-attention alone can afford us any remedy. For this reason I rely entirely on them” (Treatise, I.4.2). How did British natural and moral philosophers in the early eighteenth century think about what happens when the mind is elsewhere? How did they theorize the processes by which thoughts, fancies, memories, daydreams, and feelings come to mind without prompting either by reason or reality, by the will or by the world? Examining works by Mead, Harris, Gibbs, and Branch, I detail the role of bodily fluids and nervous spirits in “conveying the mischief” by which imagination tends to ruffle our calm. Minds are often surprised by their own habits, and various forms of regimen were recommended in these works of medical psychology and moral physiology to ‘pinion’ the imagination and still the roving thoughts. I anchor these local discussions within a broader enquiry into mind-wandering and ‘stimulus-independent thought’, and sketch a rich neurophilosophical background to Hume’s views on the bodily bases of custom and habit.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Hume 1739/1978, I.1.3, at p. 8.

  2. 2.

    Hume 1739/1978, 624.

  3. 3.

    See also Tierney-Hynes 2007 on the ‘castle-builder’.

  4. 4.

    On cognitive history compare Richardson 2001; Lloyd 2007; Smail 2008; Sutton 2000, 2002, 2007a; Tribble 2005. We hope that the risks taken in work like this of catching ‘the virus of the precursor’ are outweighed by the benefits.

  5. 5.

    /1978, 104; Traiger 1994.

  6. 6.

    James 1999; Schmitter 2006.

  7. 7.

    Singer 1966; Antrobus et al 1970; Berntsen 2009.

  8. 8.

    Smallwood and Schooler 2006; Schupak and Rosenthal 2009.

  9. 9.

    Klinger 2008.

  10. 10.

    Dreyfus 2007, 353.

  11. 11.

    Velleman 2007, 184.

  12. 12.

    Gendler 2008; Bargh 1997.

  13. 13.

    Wegner 1997.

  14. 14.

    Graybiel 1998; Ennen 2003; Yin and Knowlton 2006.

  15. 15.

    Lambie and Marcel 2002; Sutton 2007b.

  16. 16.

    Smallwood and Schooler 2006, 946.

  17. 17.

    Smallwood and Schooler 2006; Mason et al 2007; Klinger 2008; Berntsen 2009; Schupak and Rosenthal 2009.

  18. 18.

    As we’ll see, early modern thinkers treated stimulus-independent forms of mind-wandering alongside the different cases in which attention is easily captured by current stimuli.

  19. 19.

    English versions of iatromechanism are now often seen by revisionary historians as more flexible, biologically-oriented, and contextually anchored than on earlier interpretations (Ishizuka 2006). Yet the contrast is still often drawn with a rigid Cartesian model in which dynamics, sentience, and life had been evacuated from the body. For a different account of Descartes’ ideas about the complexity and flexibility of ‘automatic’ processes, and about our open organic interactions with the environment, see Sutton 1998, chapter 3; 2000.

  20. 20.

    Ishizuka, 2006.

  21. 21.

    Cunningham 1990; Sutton 1998, chapters 2 5, 7, 9.

  22. 22.

    Locke 1690/1975, Essay 2.33.6.

  23. 23.

    Locke 1690/1975, 2.33.5.

  24. 24.

    Locke 1690/1975, 2.33.4.

  25. 25.

    Locke 1690/1975, 2.33.9, 18.

  26. 26.

    Locke 1690/1975, 2.33.3, 6.

  27. 27.

    Locke 1690/1975, 2.19.1. The OED ambitiously characterizes this passage as the first instance of a distinct and metaphorical use of ‘attention’.

  28. 28.

    Locke 1690/1975, 1.1.2; Sutton 1998, chapters 7 and 9.

  29. 29.

    Locke 1690/1975 2.33.6. This is the passage brilliantly echoed by Sterne in the first chapter of The Life and Opinions of Tristram Shandy 1759/1983, 5; see Myer 1984, Sutton 1998, 207–213.

  30. 30.

    Locke 1690/1975, 2.10.4–5.

  31. 31.

    Locke 1690/1975, 2.10.4.

  32. 32.

    Descartes to Fromondus, in Descartes 1991, 61–2; and see Gaukroger 1995, 287–8.

  33. 33.

    Hume 1739/1978, 1.4.2, 218.

  34. 34.

    Hume 1739/1978, 1.4.7, 264.

  35. 35.

    Hume 1734/1993, 349. This language is echoed in the Treatise: Hume complains that metaphysical reasonings have “heated my brain” (1.4.7, 266). I agree with Marina Frasca-Spada (2003) that much of the terminology which Hume applies to ideas in the Treatise has been transformed with little alteration from a standard physiological idiom: ideas “flow in upon the mind” in a forcible or lively manner, for example, while others are “faint and languid” (Hume 1739/1978, 9), while the vividness of certain conceptions “diffuses itself … and is convey’d, as by so many pipes or canals” (ibid., 122; Frasca-Spada 2003).

  36. 36.

    Hume 1739/1978, 1.4.2, 218.

  37. 37.

    Hume 1975, 55. For Bertrand Russell, Hume’s recommendation of carelessness and inattention was not only the ultimate in self-refutation for a philosopher in particular, but also quite generally “the complete bankruptcy of reason” (Russell 1997, 239). Our default interpretive stance now is more naturalistic and affective, and thus more sympathetic.

  38. 38.

    So I agree with James A. Harris’s case, in an excellent recent paper, that the first two books of Hume’s Treatise in particular should be read against the background of many early eighteenth-century books “devoted to showing how philosophy could help with living a happier and more virtuous life, by showing the way to better regulation of the passions,” most of which books are “completely unread today” (Harris 2009). But Harris’s focus is on straightforward moral philosophy as the context, rather than on the medical-psychological and moral-physiological literature from which I sketch just a few themes in this paper. In these latter fields, there were signs prior to Hume of his idea, nicely described by Harris, that the old contest between reason and desire would be better seen as “the interaction of a panoply of feelings,” to be registered and explored in their mysterious workings by the analyst of human nature. Frasca-Spada (2003) rightly notes that Hume’s few references to common physiological theory are “impeccably well informed.”

  39. 39.

    Antrobus et al, 1970.

  40. 40.

    Sutton 2009.

  41. 41.

    Hobson & Stickgold 1994, 10–11.

  42. 42.

    Domhoff 2003, 153; see also Flanagan 2000, 58–61.

  43. 43.

    Branch also published a compendium of legal sayings in 1753, and may have been alive still in 1769. A second edition of Baxter’s Enquiry had appeared in 1737, the year before Branch’s book. For background on the Baxter-Branch debate see Dacome 2004. Dacome’s overarching case is that dreams were gradually medicalized and pathologized through the eighteenth century, as moral physiologists sought to establish “a new model of the credible mind, one in which the elimination of the vagaries of the mind was to be carried out by means of body policing,” Dacome 2004, 397. See Daston 1998 for a related broader narrative of the pathologizing of imagination in the Enlightenment. These early eighteenth-century texts also exemplify the spread of discussion about these further reaches of mental life well beyond philosophy, then as now. But further work is needed to piece together the impact and reception of works like these, and to understand how they related to moral, imaginative, cognitive, and social practices of the time.

  44. 44.

    In responding to Baxter on dreaming, Branch also offers full-scale theories of perception and memory, in seeking to demonstrate just how much the soul can do without external guidance, to prove that “our Dreams may be our own” rather than implants from spiritual beings. He also offers a rich phenomenology of dreaming, raising and effectively answering sixteen objections to his core idea that dreams are just thoughts during sleep: just as he denies their supernatural origin, so he denies that they are brute biological givens, for they take considerable psychological sophistication. For this reason Branch at least does not neatly fit Dacome’s account of the Enlightenment pathologizing of dreams, which I would argue also neglects the developmental-cognitive-affective accounts of memory and dreams in David Hartley’s Observations on Man 1749: compare Sutton 1998, chapter 13. Theories of dreams were no more homogeneous and unified (from either conceptual or applied points of view) than they are now.

  45. 45.

    Branch 1738, 45–46. The idea that external artifacts play key roles in distributed cognitive systems, transforming the demands on individual psychological resources, has been widely revived recently (Hutchins 1995; Clark 1997; Sutton 2002), but of course has itself a long history (Donald 1991; Tribble 2005; Sutton 2007a). Branch links his sense that the mind is fluid, and prone to rove, to the fact that we rely on more stable external cognitive artifacts (compare Sutton 2008). His more original point is that the residual differences between waking and dreaming mental life are due not to intrinsic physiological differences, but to the absence of social and material supports in sleep. The sociologist Maurice Halbwachs (1925/1992) likewise ran an extended analogy between dreaming, with its fragmentary, torn, confused raw materials, and the mental life of a non-social individual, to demonstrate that our waking mental life is permeated by and thoroughly sculpted by our social frameworks. Branch perhaps has less faith than Halbwachs in the coherence and stability provided in waking thought by social networks.

  46. 46.

    Branch 1738, 66. Dreaming is thus, for Branch, closer in character to imagining than to hallucinating. Compare Foulkes 1999, against Hobson’s account of dreams as delusions.

  47. 47.

    Branch 1738, 26.

  48. 48.

    On Mead and Gibbs see also Roos 2000. For Harris’s Lexicon Technicum: or, an universal English dictionary of arts and sciences (1704) I’ve used the 2nd edition (2 volumes, 1708 & 1710). Harris, who had been Boyle Lecturer in 1698, and was Secretary of the Royal Society for a year in 1709–1710, wrote an array of hack works: the DNB (IX, 13–14) says that “Harris was culpably improvident, and was generally in distress,” noting sadly that his 1719 history of Kent is “extremely inaccurate.” Thanks to Richard Yeo for advice on Harris.

  49. 49.

    Mead 1702, 20–21.

  50. 50.

    Morgan 1735, 152–4. For the earlier history of debates about animal spirits, and more detailed accounts of eighteenth-century controversies about their existence, see Jacyna 1995; Clower 1998; Sutton 1998, chapters 2, 8, 10; Rousseau 2004. Among our other current writers, Gibbs nicely compares the deniers of animal spirits to atheists. Observability is entirely irrelevant: although we can’t see God, we know he exists, so the fact that no cavity can be discovered in tubes of nervous fibre doesn’t matter, because “if the Hole was discernable, by which the Spirits pass thro’ a Fibre, it might be unfit for the Passage of so fine and rarify’d a Fluid, as the Spirits are.” Gibbs 1712, 27.

  51. 51.

    Arguing in favour of the solids, David Baynes/Kinneir explicitly recommends metaphorising the spirits, so to talk of someone being in good spirits would mean they are in health (1738, 11–12). In fact the incorporation of the language of animal spirits into economics had already begun, foreshadowing their post-Keynesian career as markers of consumer confidence (Winslow 1986, Akerlof and Shiller 2009).

  52. 52.

    Ishizuka 2006, 438–440. For more general interpretations of the phenomenology of humoral materialism, see for example Duden 1991 on the sensed “kinesthetic system of oriented flows”; Paster 1993, 1997; Rublack 2002; Seuntjens 2006; Sutton 2007a.

  53. 53.

    Mead 1702, 19.

  54. 54.

    Mead 1702, 13.

  55. 55.

    Mead 1702, 19.

  56. 56.

    Mead 1702, 17.

  57. 57.

    Gibbs 1712, 10.

  58. 58.

    Gibbs 1712, 8–12, 38–39.

  59. 59.

    Mead 1702, 14–15.

  60. 60.

    See also Roos 2000.

  61. 61.

    Gibbs 1712, 54–64.

  62. 62.

    Harris 1710, vol II, s.v. ‘spirits’.

  63. 63.

    Descartes 1972, 96. For commentary on this passage see Landormy 1902, 280–1; Krell 1990, 72–3 (on these impressions absorbed “higgledy-piggledy” as “prone to moral turpitude, lassitude, lethargy, and benumbment”); Sutton 1998, 61–2.

  64. 64.

    Descartes 1972, 96.

  65. 65.

    Mead 1702, 61.

  66. 66.

    Mead 1702, 61–62.

  67. 67.

    Mead 1702, 62.

  68. 68.

    Mead 1702, 65–67. Mead also offers a geo-sexual climatology: sometimes spirits will “without any manifest Cause at all, be hurried towards those Organs, to which at other Times they have been most frequently determined; and every one knows which they are in hot Countries and Constitutions”, 67. See Floyd-Wilson 2003 on related earlier geohumoralist assumptions.

  69. 69.

    Quoted in Barker-Benfield 1996, 9–11.

  70. 70.

    Ishizuka 2006, 452–3.

  71. 71.

    Locke 1690/1975, 2.33.16.

  72. 72.

    Sutton 2000.

  73. 73.

    Mead 1702, 70.

  74. 74.

    Locke 1690/1975, 2.33.6.

  75. 75.

    Rousseau 2008.

References

  • Akerlof, George A. & Robert J. Shiller. 2009. Animal Spirits: How Human Psychology Drives the Economy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Antrobus, John S, Jerome L. Singer, S. Goldstein, and M. Fortgang. 1970. Mindwandering and Cognitive Structure. Transactions of the New York Academy of Sciences 32, 242–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, John A. 1997. The Automaticity of Everyday Life. In The Automaticity of Everyday Life: Advances in Social Cognition, ed. R.S. Wyer, vol.10, 1–61. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker-Benfield, G.J. 1996. The Culture of Sensibility: Sex and Society in Eighteenth-Century Britain. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baynes (Kinneir), David. 1738. A New Essay on the Nerves, and the Doctrine of the Animal Spirits Rationally Considered; Shewing the Great Benefit and True Use of Bathing.... Bath: W. Innys and R. Manby

    Google Scholar 

  • Berntsen, Dorthe. 2009. Involuntary Autobiographical Memories: an Introduction to the Unbidden Past. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Branch, Thomas, 1738. Thoughts on Dreaming. London: Dodsley and Jolliffe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, Andy. 1997. Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clower, William T. 1998. The Transition from Animal Spirits to Animal Electricity: a Neuroscience Paradigm Shift. Journal of the History of the Neurosciences 7, 201–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham, Andrew. 1990. Medicine to Calm the Mind: Boerhaave’s Medical System, and Why It Was Adopted in Edinburgh. In The Medical Enlightenment of the Eighteenth Century, eds. A. Cunningham & R. French, 40–66. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dacome, Lucia. 2004. ‘To What Purpose Does it Think?’: Dreams, Sick Bodies and Confused Minds in the Age of Reason, History of Psychiatry 15, 395–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daston, Lorraine. 1998. Fear and Loathing of the Imagination in Science. Daedalus 127, 73–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, René. 1972. Treatise of Man, ed. & trans. T.S. Hall. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, René. 1991. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, vol. III: Correspondence, trans. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, D. Murdoch, & A. Kenny. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Domhoff, G. William. 2003. The Scientific Study of Dreams: Neural Networks, Cognitive Development, and Content Analysis. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Donald, Merlin. 1991. Origins of the Modern Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, Hubert L. 2007. The Return of the Myth of the Mental. Inquiry 50, 352–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duden, Barbara. 1991. The Woman Beneath the Skin: a Doctor’s Patients in Eighteenth-Century Germany. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ennen, Elizabeth. 2003. Phenomenological Coping Skills and the Striatal Memory System. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 2, 299–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, Owen. 2000. Dreaming Souls: Sleep, Dreams, and the Evolution of the Conscious Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foulkes, David. 1999. Children’s Dreaming and the Development of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Floyd-Wilson, Mary. 2003. English Ethnicity and Race in Early Modern Drama. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frasca-Spada, Marina. 2003. Belief and Animal Spirits in Hume’s Treatise. Eighteenth-Century Thought 1, 151–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaukroger, Stephen. 1995. Descartes: an Intellectual Biography. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, Tamar Szabo. 2008. Alief in Action (and Reaction). Mind & Language 23, 552–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, James. 1712. Observations of Various Eminent Cures of the King’s Evil... to Which Is Added an Essay, Concerning the Animal Spirits, and the Cure of Convulsions. London: Ralph Simpson and W. Innys, and Exeter: Philip Yeo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graybiel, Ann M. 1998. The Basal Ganglia and the Chunking of Action Repertoires. Neurobiology of Learning and Memory 70, 119–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halbwachs, Maurice. 1925/1992. The Social Frameworks of Memory, in Halbwachs. In On Collective Memory, ed. L.A. Coser. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, James A. 2009. ‘A Compleat Chain of Reasoning’: Hume’s Project in A Treatise of Human Nature, Books I and II. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 109, 129–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, John. 1708–1710. Lexicon Technicum: or, an Universal English Dictionary of Arts and Sciences, 2nd edition, 2 volumes, London: Brown et al.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartley, David. 1749/1971. Observations on Man, His Frame, His Duty, and His Expectations. London: repr. New York: Garland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, J. Allan & Robert Stickgold. 1994. Dreaming: a Neurocognitive Approach. Consciousness and Cognition 3, 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 1734/1993. A kind of history of my life (letter to Arbuthnot or Cheyne). In The Cambridge Companion to Hume, ed. D.F. Norton, 345–350. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 1739/1978. A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 1975. Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principle of Morals, ed. P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, Edwin. 1995. Cognition in the Wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ishizuka, Hisao. 2006. The Elasticity of the Animal Fibre: Movement and Life in Enlightenment Medicine. History of Science 44, 435–468.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacyna, L.S. 1995. Animal Spirits and Eighteenth-Century British Medicine. In The Comparison Between Concepts of Life-Breath in East and West, eds. Y. Kawakita, S. Sakai, & Y. Otsuka, 139–161. Tokyo, Japan & St Louis, MO: Ishiyaku Euro-America.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, Susan. 1999. Passion and Action: the Emotions in Seventeenth Century Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klinger, Eric. 2008. Daydreaming and Fantasizing: Thought Flow and Motivation. In Handbook of Imagination and Mental Simulation, eds. K.D. Markman, W.M.P. Klein, & J.A. Suhr, 225–239. New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krell, David Farrell. 1990. Of Memory, Reminiscence, and Writing: on the Verge. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lambie, John A. & Anthony J. Marcel. 2002. Consciousness and the Varieties of Emotion Experience: a Theoretical Framework. Psychological Review 109, 219–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landormy, Paul. 1902. La Mémoire Corporelle et la Mémoire Intellectuelle dans la Philosophie de Descartes. Bibliothèque du Congrès International de Philosophie 4, 259–298.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, G.E.R. 2007. Cognitive Variations: Reflections on the Unity and Diversity of the Human Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1690/1975. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mason, Malia F., Michael I. Norton, John D. Van Horn, Daniel M. Wegner, Scott T. Grafton, and C. Neil Macrae. 2007. Wandering Minds: the Default Network and Stimulus-Independent Thought. Science 315 (19 January), 393–395.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mead, Richard. 1702. A Mechanical Account of Poisons in Several Essays. London: Ralph South.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, Thomas. 1735. The Mechanical Practice of Physick.... London: T. Woodward.

    Google Scholar 

  • Myer, Valerie Grosvenor. 1984. Tristram and the Animal Spirits. In Laurence Sterne: Riddles and Mysteries, ed. V.G. Myer, 99–112. London: Barnes and Noble.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paster, Gail Kern. 1993. The Body Embarrassed: Drama and the Disciplines of Shame in Early Modern England. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paster, Gail Kern. 1997. Nervous Tension: Networks of Blood and Spirit in the Early Modern Body. In The Body in Parts, eds. D. Hillman & C. Mazzio, 107–125. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, Alan. 2001. British Romanticism and the Science of the Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roos, Anna Maria. 2000. Luminaries in Medicine: Richard Mead, James Gibbs, and Solar and Lunar Effects on the Human Body in Early Modern England. Bulletin of the History of Medicine 74, 433–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, G.S. 2004. Nervous Acts: Essays on Literature, Culture and Sensibility. London: Palgrave.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, G.S. 2008. ‘Brainomania’: Brain, Mind and Soul in the Long Eighteenth Century. British Journal for Eighteenth-Century Studies 30, 161–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rublack, Ulinka. 2002. Fluxes: the Early Modern Body and the Emotions. History Workshop Journal 53, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand. 1997. The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, vol.11. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitter, Amy M. 2006. 17th and 18th Century Theories of Emotions. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (Summer 2006 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2006/entries/emotions-17th18th/.

  • Schupak, Cynthia and Jesse Rosenthal. 2009. Excessive Daydreaming: a Case History and Discussion of Mind Wandering and High Fantasy Proneness. Consciousness and Cognition 18, 290–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seuntjens, Wolter. 2006. Vapours and Fumes, Damps and Qualms: Windy Passions in the Early-Modern Age (1600–1800). English Studies 87, 35–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, Jerome L. 1966. Daydreaming: an Introduction to the Experimental Study of Inner Experience. New York, NY: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smail, Daniel Lord. 2008. On Deep History and the Brain. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smallwood, Jonathan and Jonathan W. Schooler. 2006. The Restless Mind. Psychological Bulletin 132, 946–958.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterne, Laurence. 1759/1983. The Life and Opinions of Tristram Shandy, Gentleman, ed. I.C. Ross. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, John. 1998. Philosophy and Memory Traces: Descartes to Connectionism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, John. 2000. The Body and the Brain. In Descartes’ Natural Philosophy, eds. S. Gaukroger, J.A. Schuster, & J. Sutton, 697–722. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, John. 2002. Porous Memory and the Cognitive Life of Things. In Prefiguring Cyberculture, eds. D. Tofts, A.M. Jonson, & A. Cavallero, 130–141. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, John. 2007a. Spongy Brains and Material Memories. In Embodiment and Environment in Early Modern England, eds. M. Floyd-Wilson & G. Sullivan, 14–34. London: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, John. 2007b. Batting, Habit, and Memory: the Embodied Mind and the Nature of Skill. Sport in Society 10, 763–786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, John. 2008. Remembering. In The Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition, eds. P. Robbins & M. Aydede, 217–235. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, John. 2009. Dreaming. In The Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Psychology, eds. P. Calvo & J. Symons, 524–544. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tierney-Hynes, Rebecca. 2007. Hume, Romance, and the Unruly Imagination. Studies in English Literature 47, 641–658.

    Google Scholar 

  • Traiger, Saul. 1994. The Secret Operations of the Mind. Minds and Machines 4, 303–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tribble, Evelyn. 2005. Distributing Cognition in the Globe. Shakespeare Quarterly 56, 135–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, J. David. 2007. The Way of the Wanton. In Practical Identity and Narrative Agency, eds. C. Mackenzie & K. Atkins, 169–192. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, Daniel M. 1997. Why the Mind Wanders. In Scientific Approaches to Consciousness, eds. J. Cohen & J.W. Schooler, 295–315. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winslow, E.G. 1986. Keynes and Freud: Psychoanalysis and Keynes’s Account of the Animal Spirits of Capitalism. Social Research 53, 549–578.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yin, Henry H. & Knowlton, Barbara J. 2006. The Role of the Basal Ganglia in Habit Formation. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 7, 464–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sutton, J. (2010). Carelessness and Inattention: Mind-Wandering and the Physiology of Fantasy from Locke to Hume. In: Wolfe, C.T., Gal, O. (eds) The Body as Object and Instrument of Knowledge. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol 25. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-3686-5_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics