Skip to main content
Log in

Empathy as a necessary condition of phronesis: a line of thought for medical ethics

  • Scientific Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Empathy is a thing constantly asked for and stressed as a central skill and character trait of the good physician and nurse. To be a good doctor or a good nurse one needs to be empathic—one needs to be able to feel and understand the needs and wishes of patients in order to help them in the best possible way, in a medical, as well as in an ethical sense. The problem with most studies of empathy in medicine is that empathy is poorly defined and tends to overlap with other related things, such as emotional contagion, sympathy, or a caring personality in general. It is far from clear how empathy fits into the general picture of medical ethics and the framework of norms that are most often stressed there, such as respect for autonomy and beneficience. How are we to look upon the role and importance of empathy in medical ethics? Is empathy an affective and/or cognitive phenomenon only, or does it carry moral significance in itself as a skill and/or virtue? How does empathy attain moral importance for medicine? In this paper I will attempt to show that a comparison with the Aristotelian concept of phronesis makes it easier to see what empathy is and how it fits into the general picture of medical ethics. I will argue that empathy is a basic condition and source of moral knowledge by being the feeling component of phronesis, and, by the same power, it is also a motivation for acting in a good way.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. How to translate Aristotle’s terminology into modern English is a constant debate that is not only related to research on Ancient Greek culture and language, but also to what philosophical use can and should be made of his philosophy today. The translation by Christopher Rowe of the Nicomachean Ethics that I am referring to in this paper is by no means undisputed in comparison with earlier ones and my translations of key concepts represents a compromise that also take other translations into account (regarding these matters, see Kraut 2006).

  2. Exactly which moral excellences should be listed as necessary and sufficient to be morally good is not clear from Aristotle’s own writings. He mentions courageousness (andreia), moderation (sophrosyne), generosity, munificience (megaloprepia), great-souledness (megalopsychia), mildness, shamefulness, self control, righteousness, reasonableness and friendliness (philia). Later virtue theorists have made many changes and additions to his tentative list of possible virtues in human life, see Hursthouse 1999.

  3. Regarding “theory theory” and “simulation” definitions of empathy, see Coplan and Goldie 2011.

  4. Beauchamp and Childress, who are most often cited as the primary source for standard contemporary medical ethics in the form of principles to be balanced in forming sound ethical judgments in a dilemma, indirectly acknowledge this role for phronesis and empathy themselves by adding chapters about moral character and professional-patient relationships in the later editions of their main work Principles of Biomedical Ethics (Beauchamp and Childress 2009).

References

  • Agosta, L. 2010. Empathy in the context of philosophy. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Agosta, L. 2014. A Rumor of empathy...in Heidegger. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy (this issue).

  • Aristotle. 2002. Nicomachean ethics. Translated by C. Rowe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Battaly, H.D. 2011. Is empathy a virtue? In Empathy: Philosophical and psychological perspectives, ed. A. Coplan, and P. Goldie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, T.L., and J.F. Childress. 1979. Principles of biomedical ethics, 1st ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, T.L., and J.F. Childress. 2009. Principles of biomedical ethics, 6th ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bornemark, J. 2014. The Genesis of empathy in human development: A phenomenological reconstruction. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy (this issue).

  • Coplan, A., and P. Goldie. 2011. Introduction. In Empathy: Philosophical and psychological perspectives, ed. A. Coplan, and P. Goldie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H.-G. 1990. Wahrheit und Methode: Grundzüge einer philosophischen Hermeneutik, 6th ed. Tübingen: J. C. B. Mohr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H.-G. 1993. Über die Verborgenheit der Gesundheit. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halpern, J. 2001. From detached concern to empathy: Humanizing medical practice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halpern, J. 2014. Clinical empathy and emotional distress. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy (this issue).

  • Heidegger, M. 1986. Sein und Zeit, 16th ed. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. 1999. On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraut, R. (ed.). 2006. The Blackwell guide to Aristotle’s Nikomachean ethics. London: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. 1990a. The discernment of perception: An Aristotelian conception of private and public rationality. In: Love’s knowledge: Essays on philosophy and literature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Nussbaum, M. 1990b. Reading for life. In: Love’s knowledge: Essays on philosophy and literature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Pedersen, R. 2010. Empathy in medicine: A philosophical hermeneutic reflection. Oslo: University of Oslo, Faculty of Medicine.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrino, E.D., and D.C. Thomasma. 1993. The virtues in medical practice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J.J. 2011. Is empathy necessary for morality? In Empathy: Philosophical and psychological perspectives, ed. A. Coplan, and P. Goldie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., et al. 1996. Premotor cortex and the recognition of motor action. Cognitive Brain Research 3: 131–141.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M. 2007. The ethics of care and empathy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Svenaeus, F. 2000. The hermeneutics of medicine and the phenomenology of health: Steps towards a philosophy of medical practice. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Svenaeus, F. 2003. Hermeneutics of medicine in the wake of Gadamer: The issue of phronesis. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 24: 407–431.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D., and S. Overgaard. 2012. Empathy without isomorphism: A phenomenological account. In Empathy: From bench to bedside, ed. J. Decety. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Fredrik Svenaeus.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Svenaeus, F. Empathy as a necessary condition of phronesis: a line of thought for medical ethics. Med Health Care and Philos 17, 293–299 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-013-9487-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-013-9487-z

Keywords

Navigation