Skip to main content

Speech in Non-ideal Conditions: On Silence and Being Silenced

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Sbisà on Speech as Action

Part of the book series: Philosophers in Depth ((PID))

  • 136 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter I show that idealising assumptions can obscure conversational dynamics because they neglect power differentials that are crucial enablers of the successful performance of some speech acts. I examine how silencing is promoted by conversational norms that would defeasibly entitle linguistic agents to presume that silence indicates acceptance. I focus on Goldberg’s (Conversational Pressure: Normativity in Speech Exchanges. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020) discussion of these phenomena. Goldberg argues in support of a norm of no silent rejections, claiming that silencing is partly the result of the misapplication of this norm. He further defends the view that the norm itself is part of the solution to the problem of silencing. In the chapter I argue that Goldberg is mistaken on these points. Instead, drawing inspiration from Sbisà (Illocuzione e dislivelli di potere. In Linguaggio d’odio e autorità, ed. by Claudia Bianchi and Laura Caponetto, 63–86. Milano-Udine: Mimesis), I argue that norms of no silent rejection are temporarily enacted by means of speech acts that function as exercitive assertions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This principle prescribes that one makes one’s contribution to a conversation such ‘as is required, at the stage at which it occurs, by the accepted purpose or direction of the talk exchange in which [one is] engaged’ (Grice 1975, 26).

  2. 2.

    I set aside Goldberg’s (2020, 167) additional arguments that in serious conversations we conform to a norm NSR+ which entitles participants to presume that silence indicates belief.

  3. 3.

    However, there is a difficulty here in characterising the conditions in which NON-CONVERSATION obtains. If it were true in any circumstance in which someone is not cooperative, then it would be impossible to violate NSR, since any behaviour that seemingly violates it would create circumstances that lie outside the range of application of the norm.

  4. 4.

    Other such contexts, whilst being conversations, are cases where OUTWEIGHING EXPLANATION obtains.

  5. 5.

    Plausibly OUTWEIGHING EXPLANATION also holds when these outweighing practical reasons excuse, rather than justify, silence. Goldberg (2020, 176, fn. 55) is somewhat vague about what kinds of reasons can function as defeaters.

  6. 6.

    These responses are also used to indicate understanding. Further, it might be unclear which specific propositional content has been nodded through. I suspect this is because conversants evaluate the overall gist of a conversational contribution rather than parse it into individual sentences.

  7. 7.

    I should add that there are many cultural variations in turn-taking, the use of continuants, and so forth. I gloss these over here because I do not think that such variation invalidates my main point.

  8. 8.

    Without an explicit signal the potentially harmful assertion would be seamlessly incorporated into the common ground (Stalnaker 2002).

  9. 9.

    We also disapprove of people who do not resist oppression when they have an obligation to do so. In some cases, these people have a moral obligation to speak. Hence, we censor them for their silence. I have discussed these cases when considering Goldberg’s third piece of evidence for NSR.

  10. 10.

    This would be something akin to a discursive injustice that occurs when a linguistic agent performs a speech act other than the one she intends, and attempts, to perform despite legitimately expecting to be able successfully to perform it (Kukla 2014). Thanks to Laura Caponetto for pressing this point.

  11. 11.

    See Sbisà (1999) on the manner in which ideological content is often presupposed rather than explicitly articulated in speech exchanges.

  12. 12.

    Goldberg could respond that the double harm occurs only when a silenced individual is not aware that she has been silenced or that others have been. It is hard to think such a person exists. Since Goldberg’s arguments are driven by the desire to portray oppressed individuals as epistemically rational, it does not seem a gain to explain the double harm in terms of their alleged ignorance of blatantly obvious facts about oppression.

  13. 13.

    This is not to deny that sometimes silence is ambiguous and hard to interpret.

  14. 14.

    This claim presupposes that participants have formulated doxastic responses to the assertions they have witnessed. Goldberg (2020, 96–97) argues that participants in a conversation owe it to speakers to evaluate properly, in accordance with the relevant epistemic standards, speakers’ competence with regard to the asserted content. Participants who do not do this, barring excuses or justifications, are disrespectful to speakers. Hence, participants have an obligation to either reject or accept the asserted contents. That is, they have an obligation to formulate a doxastic response.

  15. 15.

    Note that the benefit to each of knowing that 1000 participants agree as opposed to 999 is so small that it might be outweighed by the effort required to communicate. Communication is always effortful including when such communication is achieved by choosing to be silent. Goldberg acknowledges that something like this might be the case and classifies these circumstances as a defeating condition.

  16. 16.

    This is the argument implicitly deployed by Goldberg (2020) on p. 204.

  17. 17.

    This argument for efficiency relies on assumptions that could be questioned. The first is that silence is not a mark. I have hinted above to reasons why this might not be true. The second is that silence is not effortful. This is also unlikely to be true since it might require resisting impulses to respond. In order properly to assess Goldberg’s claim one would need to be clear about his interpretation of efficiency.

  18. 18.

    I would like to thank the editors of this volume for their helpful suggestions. Jessica Brown, Catarina Dutilh Novaes, Greg Restall, and other members of Archè offered useful comments that greatly improved this chapter. Special thanks to Sandy Goldberg for making every speech exchange with him a conversation.

References

  • Eddo-Lodge, Reni. 2017. Why Iʼm no Longer Talking to White People about Race. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Jane. 2020. The Epistemic and the Zetetic. The Philosophical Review 129 (4): 501–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, Sanford C. 2020. Conversational Pressure: Normativity in Speech Exchanges. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul H. 1975. Logic and Conversation. In Syntax and Semantics, Vol. 3: Speech Acts, edited by Paul Cole and Jerry Morgan. New York: Academic Press. Reprinted in Studies in the Way of Words (1989), 22–40. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henderson, David. 2020. Are Epistemic Norms Fundamentally Social Norms? Episteme 17 (3): 281–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kendrick, Kobin H., and Francisco Torreira. 2015. The Timing and Construction of Preference: A Quantitative Study. Discourse Processes 52 (4): 255–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, Rebecca. 2014. Performative Force, Convention, and Discursive Injustice. Hypatia 29 (2): 440–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langton, Rae. 1993. Speech Acts and Unspeakable Acts. Philosophy and Public Affairs 22 (4): 293–330.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindström, Anna, and Marja-Leena Sorjonen. 2013. Affiliation in Conversation. In The Handbook of Conversation Analysis, ed. Jack Sidnell and Tanya Stivers, 350–369. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, Charles W. 2004. Ideal Theoryʼ as Ideology. In Moral Psychology: Feminist Ethics and Social Theory, ed. Eggy DesAutels and Margaret M.U. Walker, 163–181. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morton, Adam. 2012. Bounded Thinking: Intellectual Virtues for Limited Agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ranjbar, Marie A. 2017. Silence, Silencing, and (In)Visibility: The Geopolitics of Tehranʼs Silent Protests. Hypatia 32 (3): 609–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sbisà, Marina. 1999. Ideology and the Persuasive Use of Presupposition. In Language and Ideology. Selected Papers from the 6th International Pragmatics, edited by Jef Verschueren, 492–509. Antwerp: International Pragmatics Association. Reprinted in Marina Sbisà (forthcoming), Essays on Speech Acts and Other Topics in Pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2018. Varieties of Speech Act Norms. In Normativity and Variety of Speech Actions, edited by Maciej Witek and Iwona Witczak-Plisiecka, 23–50. Leiden: Brill. Reprinted in Marina Sbisà (forthcoming), Essays on Speech Acts and Other Topics in Pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020. Illocuzione e dislivelli di potere. In Linguaggio d’odio e autorità, ed. by Claudia Bianchi and Laura Caponetto, 63–86. Milano-Udine: Mimesis. Transl. as Illocution and Power Imbalance in Marina Sbisà (forthcoming), Essays on Speech Acts and Other Topics in Pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, Robert. 2002. Common Ground. Linguistics and Philosophy 25: 701–721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stivers, Tanya. 2008. Stance, Alignment, and Affiliation During Storytelling: When Nodding Is a Token of Affiliation. Research on Language and Social Interaction 41 (1): 31–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tanesini, Alessandra. 2018. Eloquent Silences: Silence and Dissent. In Voicing Dissent: The Ethics and Epistemology of Making Disagreement Public, ed. Casey R. Johnson, 109–128. New York and London: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Woolley, Susan W. 2012. The Silence Itself Is Enough of a Statementʼ: The Day of Silence and LGBTQ Awareness Raising. Anthropology and Education Quarterly 43 (3): 271–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alessandra Tanesini .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Tanesini, A. (2023). Speech in Non-ideal Conditions: On Silence and Being Silenced. In: Caponetto, L., Labinaz, P. (eds) Sbisà on Speech as Action. Philosophers in Depth. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-22528-4_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics