Skip to main content
Log in

Taming Wickedness: Towards an Implementation Framework for Medical Ethics

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Health Care Analysis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

“Wicked” problems are characterized by intractable complexity, uncertainty, and conflict between individuals or institutions, and they inhabit almost every corner of medical ethics. Despite wide acceptance of the same ethical principles, we nevertheless disagree about how to formulate such problems, how to solve them, what would count as solving them, or even what the possible solutions are. That is, we don’t always know how best to implement ethical ideals in messy real-world contexts. I sketch an implementation framework for medical ethics that can help clarify wicked problems and organize further ethics research toward their resolutions. This framework describes the procedural variables that work alongside substantive ethical ideals to deliver ethical decisions in complex real-world situations. Using controversial GM mosquito research as an example, I illustrate how the generalizable relationships between the variables clarify emerging ethical guidelines of research governance and provide a pathway to extend these guidelines in a way consistent with our ethical intuitions across a wide range of research and public health ethics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The term ‘wicked problem’ was first widely used in the policy and organizational sciences. See Rittel and Webber [1]. The characteristics of ‘deep disagreement’ are explored in Fogelin [2] and Taylor [3].

  2. Evaluating efficacy will entail controlling for differences in provider training and patient compliance, for example. But these factors significantly affect effectiveness. Thus, clinical trials evaluating a therapy’s efficacy may be a poor guide to its effectiveness.

  3. This includes not only the principles in their most abstract form, but also in their more concrete, mid-level forms, such as that respect for persons requires the consent of research subjects without coercion or undue influence, or that justice requires the equitable recruitment of research subjects and a fair distribution of research risks and benefits across populations.

  4. Some procedural issues are addressed in a systematic way within the broader deliberative democracy movement. See, for example, National Coalition for Dialogue and Deliberation [35].

  5. In the organ allocation example, the tightness of a proxy is loosely analogous to the continuum described by decision theory under the rubric of ‘signaling.’ On one end of the continuum are ‘costly signals’ and on the other end, ‘cheap talk’ [37]. In the UNOS scheme, the fabrication of blood-level indicators would indeed be a costly signal, which explains why these levels are a tight proxy for medical need. However, the concept of a tight proxy articulated here is more expansive than the decision-theoretic concept, and can describe relationships that have nothing to do with signaling. For example, clearance by double-blind peer review may be a tighter proxy for the eventual truth of an academic article’s claims than pay-to-publish schemes are. But that fact, if true, is not explained by signaling in the decision-theoretic sense.

References

  1. Rittel, H., & Webber, M. (1973). Dilemmas in a general theory of planning. Policy Sci, 4(2), 155–169. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01405730

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Fogelin, R. (1985). The logic of deep disagreement. Informal Logic, 7(1), 3–11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Taylor, E. (2018). Beyond deep disagreement: paralysis as a kind of argument failure in medicine. RIFL, 12(1), 65–74

    Google Scholar 

  4. Alford, J., & Head, B. W. (2017). Wicked and less wicked problems: a typology and a contingency framework. Policy and Society, 36(3), 397–413. https://doi.org/10.1080/14494035.2017.1361634

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. van der Bruggen, K. (2008). Critical infrastructures and responsibility: a conceptual exploration. Safety Science, 46(7), 1137–1148. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ssci.2007.06.003

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Williams, G. (2006). ‘Infrastructures of responsibility’: the moral tasks of institutions. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 23(2), 207–221

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Periyakoil, V. (2007). Taming wicked problems in modern health care systems. J Palliat Med, 10(3), 658–659. https://doi.org/10.1089/jpm.2007.9955

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Murphy, P., et al. (2000). Description of the SUPPORT intervention study to understand prognoses and preferences for outcomes and risks of treatments. Journal of the American Geriatrics Society, 48(5), S154–161

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  9. Lynn, J., et al. (2000). Ineffectiveness of the SUPPORT intervention: review of explanations. Journal of the American Geriatrics Society, 48(5), S206–213

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  10. Lynn, J., et al. (2000). Rethinking fundamental assumptions: SUPPORT’s implications for future reform. Journal of the American Geriatrics Society, 48(5), S214–221

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  11. Lavery, J. V. (2018). ‘Wicked problems’, community engagement and the need for an implementation science for research ethics. J Med Ethics, 44(3), 163–164. https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2016-103573

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Buchanan, D., & Miller, F. (2006). Justice and fairness in the Kennedy Krieger Institute lead paint study: the ethics of public health research on less expensive, less effective interventions. Am J Public Health, 96, 781–787. https://doi.org/10.2105/AJPH.2005.063719

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Fleck, L. (2012). Pharmacogenomics and personalized medicine: wicked problems, ragged edges and ethical precipices. N Biotechnol, 29(6), 757–768. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.nbt.2012.03.002

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  14. Hannigan, B., & Coffey, M. (2011). Where the wicked problems are: the case of mental health. Health Policy, 101(3), 220–227. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.healthpol.2010.11.002

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Ricciardi, A., Blackburn, T., Carton, J., et al. (2017). Invasion science: a horizon scan of emerging challenges and opportunities. Trends Ecol Evol, 32(6), 464–474. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tree.2017.03.007

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Muirhead, W. (2012). When four principles are too many: bloodgate, integrity and an action-guiding model of ethical decision making in clinical practice. Journal of Medical Ethics, 38(4), 195–196. https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2011-100136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Sullivan, W. M. (2000). Medicine under threat: professionalism and professional identity. Canadian Medical Association Journal, 162(5), 673–675

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  18. Richardson, H., & Belsky, L. (2004). The ancillary-care responsibilities of medical researchers: an ethical framework for thinking about the clinical care that researchers owe their subjects. The Hastings Center Report, 34(1), 25–33. https://doi.org/10.2307/3528248

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Kaldjian, L., Weir, R., & Duffy, T. (2005). A clinician’s approach to clinical ethical reasoning. Journal of General Internal Medicine, 20(3), 306–311. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1525-1497.2005.40204.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. National Institutes of Health (2016). Guiding principles for ethical research. https://www.nih.gov/health-information/nih-clinical-research-trials-you/guiding-principles-ethical-research

  21. Tannahill, A. (2008). Beyond evidence—to ethics: a decision-making framework for health promotion, public health and health improvement. Health Promotion International, 23(4), 380–390. https://doi.org/10.1093/heapro/dan032

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Childress, J., et al. (2002). Public health ethics: mapping the terrain. Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 30(2), 170–178. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1748-720X.2002.tb00384.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Public Health Leadership Society (2002). Principles of the ethical practice of public health. https://www.apha.org/-/media/files/pdf/membergroups/ethics/ethics_brochure.ashx

  24. Kass, N. (2001). An ethics framework for public health. The American Journal of Public Health, 91(11), 1776–1782. https://doi.org/10.2105/AJPH.91.11.1776

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  25. National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research (1976). The Belmont Report. https://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/regulations-and-policy/belmont-report/index.html

  26. United States Department of Health and Human Services (1991). Federal policy for the protection of human subjects (‘Common Rule’). https://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/regulations-and-policy/regulations/common-rule/index.html

  27. Giubilini, A., Milnes, S., & Savulescu, J. (2016). The medical ethics curriculum in medical schools: present and future. Journal of Clinical Ethics, 27(2), 129–145

    Google Scholar 

  28. Eccles, M., & Mittman, B. (2006). Welcome to implementation science. Implement Sci, 1(1), https://doi.org/10.1186/1748-5908-1-1

  29. Dawson, L., Strathdee, S., London, A., et al. (2018). Addressing ethical challenges in HIV prevention research with people who inject drugs. J Med Ethics, 44(3), 149–158. https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2015-102895

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Consolidated Framework for Implementation Research (2019). https://cfirguide.org/constructs/

  31. Bauer, M., Damschroder, L., Hagedorn, H., et al. (2015). An introduction to implementation science for the non-specialist. BMC Psychol, 3(32), https://doi.org/10.1186/s40359-015-0089-9

  32. Beauchamp, T., & Childress, J. (2013). Principles of Biomedical Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  33. Gert, B. (1997). Bioethics: A Return to Fundamentals. New York: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  34. Childress, et al. (2002). Public health ethics: mapping the terrain. Journal of Law Medicine and Ethics, 30(2), 170–178

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. National Coalition for Dialogue and Deliberation (2009). Engagement Streams Framework. http://www.ncdd.org/files/rc/2014_Engagement_Streams_Guide_Web.pdf

  36. Gutmann, A., & Thompson, D. (1996). Democracy and Disagreement. Cambridge, Mass: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  37. Farrell, J., & Rabin, M. (1996). Cheap talk. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 10(3), 103–118. https://doi.org/10.1257/jep.10.3.103

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. LaPointe, D., et al. (2015). The psychosocial and independent living donor advocate evaluation and post-surgery care of living donors. Journal of Clinical Psychology in Medical Settings, 22(2–3), 136–149. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10880-015-9426-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. World Health Organization (2019). Mosquito-Borne Diseases. https://www.who.int/neglected_diseases/vector_ecology/mosquito-borne-diseases/en/

  40. Marshall, J., & Taylor, C. (2009). Malaria control with transgenic mosquitoes. PLoS Med, 6(2), e1000020. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pmed.1000020

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. James, S., Collins, F. H., Welkhoff, P. A., et al. (2018). Pathway to deployment of gene drive mosquitoes as a potential biocontrol tool for elimination of malaria in sub-saharan africa: recommendations of a scientific working group. Am J Trop Med Hyg, 98(6), 1–49. https://doi.org/10.4269/ajtmh.18-0083

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Neves, M., & Druml, C. (2017). Ethical implications of fighting malaria with CRISPR/Cas9. BMJ Global Health, 2(3), e000396. https://doi.org/10.1136/bmjgh-2017-000396

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Neuhaus, C. (2018). Community engagement and field trials of genetically modified insects and animals. Hastings Center Report, 48(1), 25–36. https://doi.org/10.1002/hast.808

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Kolopack, P. A., & Lavery, J. V. (2017). Informed consent in field trials of gene-drive mosquitoes. Gates Open Res, 1(14), https://doi.org/10.12688/gatesopenres.12771.1

  45. The National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine (2016). Committee on Gene Drive Research in Non-Human Organisms: Recommendations for Responsible Conduct. https://doi.org/10.17226/23405

  46. UNICEF/UNDP/World Bank/WHO Special Programme for Research and Training in Tropical Diseases. (‎2015)‎. Biosafety for human health and the environment in the context of the potential use of genetically modified mosquitoes (‎GMMs)‎: a tool for biosafety training based on courses in Africa, Asia and Latin America, 2008–2011. World Health Organization. https://apps.who.int/iris/handle/10665/180388

  47. King, K. F., Kolopack, P. A., Merritt, M., et al. (2014). Community engagement and the human infrastructure of global health research. BMC Med Ethics, 15(84), https://doi.org/10.1186/1472-6939-15-84

  48. Mcnaughton, D., & Duong, T. (2014). Designing a community engagement framework for a new dengue control method: a case study from central Vietnam. PLoS Negl Trop Dis, 8(5), e2794. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pntd.0002794;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Kolopack, P. A., Parsons, J., & Lavery, J. V. (2015). What makes community engagement effective?: lessons from the eliminate dengue program in Queensland Australia. PLoS Negl Trop Dis, 9(4), e0003713. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pntd.0003713

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  50. Sunstein, C. (2002). The law of group polarization. Journal of Political Philosophy, 10(2), 175–195. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9760.00148

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Stirling, A. (2014). Towards innovation democracy: participation, responsibility and precaution in the politics of science and technology. Innovation: Managing Risk, Not Avoiding It. Evidence and Case Studies. London: Government Office of Science

    Google Scholar 

  52. Tait, J. (2009). Upstream engagement and the governance of science: the shadow of the genetically modified crops experience in Europe. EMBO Reports, 10, 8–22. https://doi.org/10.1038/embor.2009.138

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Erin Taylor.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Taylor, E. Taming Wickedness: Towards an Implementation Framework for Medical Ethics. Health Care Anal 30, 197–214 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-022-00445-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-022-00445-5

Keywords

Navigation