Skip to main content
Log in

Mechanisms and generative material models

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Mechanisms consist of component parts and processes organized in a specific way to produce changes that may give rise to one or more phenomena. I aim to examine the generative mechanism of generative material models in the production of new material models. A generative material model in biology is a living material model (such as model organisms) that is capable of generating new material models (e.g., new model organisms). I contend that generative mechanisms of a generative material model are not to be conflated with biological mechanisms: the former is a mechanism manipulated and altered by the modeler while the latter is a naturally occurring mechanism. I examine the ways in which idealization may contribute to the generative mechanism in generating new model organisms. I articulate that the component parts and activities in a generative mechanism are to a large extent shaped by idealization in generative material modeling. Although biological mechanisms do have a role to play in the generation of model organisms, I propose that we shall view the generative mechanism as a hybrid of biological mechanisms and modeling activities. I shall argue that the notion of generative mechanisms as hybrid mechanisms is different from the extant conceptions of mechanisms in various aspects.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Idealization in a generative material model involves distortion of the original component parts (e.g., changing genetic sequences and constitutions, protein–protein interactions, etc). Idealization as an activity of distortion has been discussed in McMullin (1985), Jones (2005) and Tee (2019). Weber (2014) claims that idealization can be applied to microorganisms by constructing isolated clone of bacteria which does not exist in nature. This process of idealization involves the manipulation of the bacteria grown in culture.

  2. My distinction between generative mechanisms and biological mechanisms is one that aims to demonstrate that the former (being a hybrid of biological mechanisms and modeling activities) is a distinct kind of biological mechanism that is capable of generating a new material model (organism); whereas the latter (viz. biological mechanisms) consists of naturally occurring component parts and processes which do not generate new material model (e.g., neurotransmission is a biological mechanism that does not generate new material model). Generative mechanisms are by no means unbiological in virtue of the intervention of modelers. In fact, generative mechanisms are biological in the first place (as many of its parts and processes are biological or biochemical)—which serves as the biological basis from which new material model (organism) such as new stem cells or yeasts could be generated under the manipulation of modelers. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for pushing me on this point.

  3. Peschard (2011) provides an account of a generative model for abstract mathematical models, which I shall call it a generative abstract model, which is to be distinguished from Fagan’s notion of a generative material model (to be discussed below). Both Fagan and Peschard contend that the objective of a generative model is to construct new models instead of representing the target phenomenon.

  4. To my best knowledge, Fagan’s (2016) account is the first account of generative material models. Though Peschard (2011) provides the first account of a generative model, hers is about generative abstract models because she focuses on abstract modeling.

  5. Fagan does not use the term ‘generative mechanism’. However, she does use the terms such as ‘mechanisms of cell development’ and ‘molecular mechanisms’ to elucidate the mechanisms by which a model organism produces new model organisms.

  6. Some philosophers view idealization introduced in stem cell biology as a methodological bias. For example, Minelli and Baedke (2014) reject the strategy of idealizing patterns of individual variation in modeling the developmental mechanism of a stem cell model. They argue that by preserving the developmental pattern of variation from idealization, our understanding of the developmental plasticity and evolvability of a model organism could be enhanced.

  7. Fagan does not deny the importance of modeling in the generation of new model organisms. What I am trying to show is that her account of generative mechanisms is complying with the extant received notions of biological mechanisms according to which a biological mechanism consists of naturally occurring material parts and the interaction between these parts.

  8. I anticipate that some critics may argue that hESCs should be treated as a biological entity rather than a model organism, therefore the generative mechanism of hESCs should also be viewed as a biological mechanism rather than a hybrid mechanism. To reply, it is important to bear in mind that hESCs are handled and cultured by biologists in the laboratory, and they are not naturally occurring biological entities. Besides, Fagan’s (2016) paper takes hESCs as a model organism despite her focus on the generative mechanism of hESCs is skewed towards biological mechanism.

  9. The first human embryonic stem cell line (hESCs) was created by James Thomson’s team (1998) in University of Wisconsin.

  10. Cf. Huber and Keuck (2013) who deny, in passing, the compatibility between the development of model organisms and idealization (p. 389).

  11. The integration of mathematical explanation and mechanistic explanation has also been recognized to be important in explaining qualitative explanandum, see Bechtel (2013) and Brigandt (2013).

  12. I do not take the generic account of a mechanism as a shortcoming.

  13. An external agent that plays a role in imposing induced organization, according to Glennan and Illari, is “like when a host arranges the seating of guests at a dinner party” (2018, p. 97).

  14. Brigandt (2013) states that the robustness of a biological system is “an evolved ability where the organismal system actively responds to disturbances, so as during embryonic development to permit the reliable generation of the adult phenotype in the face of perturbations to development, and subsequently to maintain functioning and an adaptive phenotype in a changing environment” (p. 486). This sentence on the characteristics of robustness during embryonic development of a biological system is quite relevant to the generative mechanism discussed in this paper, as generative mechanisms typically involve robust embryonic development of a new model organism. Brigandt further contends that the phenomenon of robustness shows that “sometimes the components of a mechanism cannot be clearly individuated (which also entails that the boundary between the mechanism and entities not belonging to the mechanism is blurry)” (p. 489. Original emphases).

References

  • Andersen, H. (2014). A field guide to mechanisms: Part II. Philosophy Compass, 9(4), 284–293.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ankeny, R., & Leonelli, S. (2011). What’s so special about model organisms? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 42, 313–323.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baetu, T. M. (2018). Mechanisms in molecular biology. In S. Glennan & P. Illari (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of mechanisms and mechanical philosophy (pp. 308–318). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. W. (2009). Idealization and modeling. Synthese, 169, 427–446.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2011). Mechanism and biological explanation. Philosophy of Science, 78, 533–557.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2012). Understanding endogenously active mechanisms: A scientific and philosophical challenge. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2, 233–248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2013). From molecules to behavior and the clinic: Integration in chronobiology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44, 493–502.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2015). Can mechanistic explanation be reconciled with scale-free constitution and dynamics? Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 53, 84–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanist alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 421–441.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2013). Systems biology and the integration of mechanistic explanation and mathematical explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44, 477–492.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2002). Interlevel experiments and multilevel mechanisms in the neuroscience of memory. Philosophy of Science, 69, S83–S97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2008). Thinking again about biological mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 75, 958–969.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Donato Rodríguez, X., & Arroyo-Santos, A. (2012). The structure of idealization in biological theories: The case of the Wright–Fisher model. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 43(1), 11–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elowitz, M. B., & Leibler, S. (2000). A synthetic oscillatory network of transcriptional regulators. Nature, 403, 335–338.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fagan, M. B. (2016). Generative models: Human embryonic stem cells and multiple modeling relations. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 56, 122–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69(S3), S342–S353.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2008). Mechanisms. In M. Curd & S. Psillos (Eds.), Routledge companion to the philosophy of science (pp. 376–384). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2010). Ephemeral mechanisms and historical explanation. Erkenntnis, 72(2), 251–266.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2017). The new mechanical philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S., & Illari, P. (2018). Varieties of mechanisms. In S. Glennan & P. Illari (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of mechanisms and mechanical philosophy (pp. 91–103). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardesty, R. A. (2018). Much ado about mice: Standard-setting in model organism research. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 68–69, 15–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huber, L., & Keuck, L. (2013). Mutant mice: Experimental organisms as materialised models in biomedicine. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44, 385–391.

    Google Scholar 

  • Illari, P. M., & Williamson, J. (2010). Function and organization: Comparing the mechanisms of protein synthesis and natural selection. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 41, 279–291.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ioannidis, S., & Psillos, S. (2018). Mechanisms, counterfactuals, and laws. In S. Glennan & P. Illari (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of mechanisms and mechanical philosophy (pp. 144–156). London & New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, M. (2005). Idealization and abstraction: A framework. In M. Jones & N. Cartwright (Eds.), Idealization XII: Correcting the model. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaiser, M. I. (2018). The components and boundaries of mechanisms. In S. Glennan & P. Illari (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of mechanisms and mechanical philosophy (pp. 116–130). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusstatscher, S., Sandor, Z., Szabo, S., Seddon, A., & Böhlen, P. (1995). Different molecular forms of basic fibroblast growth factor (bFGF) accelerate duodenal ulcer healing in rats. The Journal of Pharmacology and Experimental Therapeutics, 275(1), 456–461.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A. (2013). Three kinds of new mechanism. Biology and Philosophy, 28, 99–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Love, A. C. (2018). Developmental mechanisms. In S. Glennan & P. Illari (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of mechanisms and mechanical philosophy (pp. 332–347). London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1985). Galilean idealization. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 16, 247–273.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minelli, A., & Baedke, J. (2014). Model organisms in evo-devo: Promises and pitfalls of the comparative approach. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 36(1), 42–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh, J. (2018). Building trust, removing doubt? Robustness analysis and climate modeling. In E. A. Lloyd & E. Winsberg (Eds.), Climate modelling: Philosophical and conceptual issues (pp. 297–321). Switzerland: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peschard, I. (2011). Making sense of modeling: Beyond representation. European Journal for Philosophy of Science., 1(3), 335–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2011). Modeling reality. Synthese, 180, 19–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rice, C. (2018). Idealized models, holistic distortions, and universality. Synthese, 195(6), 2795–2819.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shamblott, M. J., Axelman, J., Wang, S., Bugg, E. M., Littlefield, J. W., Donovan, P. J., et al. (1998). Derivation of pluripotent stem cells from cultured human primordial germ cells. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 95(23), 13726–13731.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skipper, R. A., Jr., & Millstein, R. L. (2005). Thinking about evolutionary mechanisms: Natural selection. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 327–347.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterrett, S. G. (2017). Experimentation on analogue models. In L. Magnani & T. Bertolotti (Eds.), Springer handbook of model-based science (pp. 857–878). Switzerland: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tee, S.-H. (2018). Constructing reality with models. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1673-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tee, S.-H. (2019). Fictional experimental modeling in biology: In vivo representation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 74, 1–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. A., Itskovitz-Eldor, J., Shapiro, S. S., Waknitz, M. A., Swiergiel, J. J., Marshall, V. S., et al. (1998). Embryonic stem cell lines derived from human blastocysts. Science, 282(5391), 1145–1147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Torres, P. J. (2009). A modified conception of mechanisms. Erkenntnis, 71(2), 233–251.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (2004). Philosophy of experimental biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (2014). Experimental modeling in biology: In vivo representation and stand-ins as modeling strategies. Philosophy of Science, 81(5), 756–769.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2007). Three kinds of idealization. The Journal of Philosophy, 104(12), 639–659.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2013). Simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2002). What is a mechanism? A counterfactual account. Philosophy of Science, 69(S3), S366–S377.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sim-Hui Tee.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Tee, SH. Mechanisms and generative material models. Synthese 198, 6139–6157 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02454-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02454-9

Keywords

Navigation