Skip to main content

Maddy On The Multiverse

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Reflections on the Foundations of Mathematics

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 407))

Abstract

Penelope Maddy has recently addressed the set-theoretic multiverse , and expressed reservations on its status and merits (Maddy, Set-theoretic foundations. In: Caicedo et al (eds) Foundations of mathematics. Essays in honor of W. Hugh Woodin’s 60th birthday. Contemporary mathematics. American Mathematical Society, Providence, pp. 289–322, 2017). The purpose of the paper is to examine her concerns, by using the interpretative framework of set-theoretic naturalism . I first distinguish three main forms of ‘multiversism’ , and then I proceed to analyse Maddy ’s concerns. Among other things, I take into account salient aspects of multiverse-related mathematics, in particular, research programmes in set theory for which the use of the multiverse seems to be crucial, and show how one may provide responses to Maddy ’s concerns based on a careful analysis of ‘multiverse practice’.

I wish to thank the anonymous referee for suggesting several improvements. I am also hugely indebted to Penelope Maddy for useful comments and further theoretical inputs, as well as for discussing and reading earlier drafts of this paper. Finally, I would like to thank the editors, in particular Deborah Kant and Deniz Sarikaya, for their support and help, both during the FOMUS conference at Bielefeld and the preparation of this work.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    I am indebted to Koellner (2014) for this articulation of the pluralist/non-pluralist positions.

  2. 2.

    This seems to be Väänänen ’s point of view in Väänänen (2014). Väänänen ’s main goal is to articulate a position which allows one to express the absolute undecidability of set-theoretic statements which are currently undecidable in several important theories (such as ZFC plus large cardinals ). See also Sect. 3.2.1.

  3. 3.

    It should be noted that the article mentioned is, in fact, an appraisal of different competing foundations of mathematics, also including set theory, and of the roles such competing foundations carry out. Only one specific section of the article is explicitly devoted to examining the prospects of the set-theoretic multiverse .

  4. 4.

    Throughout the paper, I shall use ‘Maddian naturalism ’ and ‘set-theoretic naturalism ’ (sometimes, just ‘naturalism’) interchangeably. Of course, there are many other ways to spell out naturalism in the philosophy of mathematics. An overview of all such positions is in Paseau (2016).

  5. 5.

    Maddy herself has put forward and discussed the central aspects of set-theoretic naturalism as a form of ‘second philosophy’ in several works, starting with Maddy (1996). Second philosophy is further delineated in Maddy (2007), as well as in Maddy (2011).

  6. 6.

    In Antos et al. (2015), the authors adopt a classification based on the realism/non-realism divide. Hamkins ’ conception, for instance, counts as realist, whereas the Hyperuniverse Programme as non-realist. Väänänen proposes a different classification in Väänänen (2014), pp. 191–2: he divides conceptions into countable (Hyperuniverse Programme ), full (Hamkins ) and set-generic (Woodin , Steel ).

  7. 7.

    See Zermelo (1930). An examination (and reprise) of Zermelo ’s proof is in Martin (2001).

  8. 8.

    For Zermelo ’s height potentialism , see Linnebo (2013) and Ternullo and Friedman (2016). Of course, historically, Zermelo did not construe the ideas contained in Zermelo (1930) in the current multiversist terms. Väänänen suggests a different reason why Zermelo ’s characterisation of V  ought not to be viewed as an instance of the multiverse. He notes that believing in the existence of an inaccessible κ in V  means accepting the axiom: ‘∃κ inaccessible’, which, although clearly independent from ZFC , is not indeterminate in the same sense as, say, CH is. According to Väänänen , the multiverse phenomenon takes place in the presence of statements which are indeterminate in the sense specified. In other terms, if V  is V κ, where κ is the least strongly inaccessible cardinal, then ‘∃κ inaccessible’ is just false, and there is no ‘parallel’ V  with inaccessibles. Cf. Väänänen (2014), p. 187. Finally, one could resist this interpretation of Zermelo ’s conception by asserting that the set-theoretic hierarchy is, in fact, fully actual in height and width. For a fuller examination of the actualism /potentialism dichotomy, see Antos et al. (2015) or Koellner (2009).

  9. 9.

    Cf. Shelah (2003), p. 211. It is worth quoting the passage in full: ‘My mental picture is that we have many possible set theories, all conforming to ZFC . I do not feel “a universe of ZFC ” is like “the Sun”, it is rather like “a human being” or “a human being of some fixed nationality”’.

  10. 10.

    See Väänänen (2014), pp. 196–202.

  11. 11.

    For Woodin ’s set-generic multiverse , see Woodin (2011), although earlier instances of multiverse thinking may also be found, as will be shown later in this paper, in Woodin (2001). Steel ’s conception of the set-generic multiverse is in Steel (2014).

  12. 12.

    For this conception, see, essentially, Arrigoni and Friedman (2013), and Antos et al. (2015).

  13. 13.

    See Sects. 3.4.1 and 3.4.2 later in this paper. Further technical details concerning the use of V -logic and the ‘reduction to the hyperuniverse ’ may be found in Antos et al. (2015) and in Friedman (2016).

  14. 14.

    Moreover, some of these axioms (such as Axiom 2d [Amalgamation]) are not valid in Woodin ’s multiverse. Woodin has also tried to axiomatise the generic multiverse , by introducing the aforementioned ‘multiverse laws’. However, these laws are so very much ad hoc that one would naturally refrain from viewing them as axioms .

  15. 15.

    This is because, given any two theories T 1 and T 2 extending ZFC having the same consistency strength as ZFC +“exist infinitely many Woodin cardinals ”, then at least up to \(\varPi ^1_\omega \) ‘statements’ (second-order arithmetic), we have that either T 1 ⊆T 2 or T 2 ⊆T 1, and this result may be extended to slightly more complex sentences.

  16. 16.

    Some such foundational roles are also re-stated by Maddy in the paper published in the present volume.

  17. 17.

    Rather unsurprisingly, among the spurious ones, Maddy mentions ‘Metaphysical Insight ’, that is, the pretension that set theory provides us with an account of what mathematical objects really are, and ‘Epistemic Source ’, viz. the idea that set theory provides us with an account of what mathematical knowledge is.

  18. 18.

    The maxim ‘maximize ’ was also introduced by Maddy in (1996). The application of the maxim to our conception of V  implies that this has as many ‘objects’ as possible. It should be noted that, while, theoretically, maxims may be in tension with each other, they ought to be seen as having the same foundational (normative) content (cf. Maddy 1997, pp. 211–2). Among other things, this is shown by the fact that the iterative concept of set (which is generally taken to motivate V ) is also naturally construed as being ‘maximal’ (for this, also see Wang 1974, Boolos 1971 or Gödel 1947). Cf. also Maddy (1996), in particular, pp. 507–12.

  19. 19.

    Maddy (2017), p. 293.

  20. 20.

    See Hamkins (2012), p. 417. Hamkins says: ‘Often the clearest way to refer to a set concept is to describe the universe of sets in which it is instantiated, and in this article I shall simply identify a set concept with the model of set theory to which it gives rise. By adopting a particular concept of set, we in effect adopt that universe as our current mathematical universe; we jump inside and explore the nature of set theory offered by that universe.’

  21. 21.

    FBP was introduced by Mark Balaguer in (1995). See also Balaguer (1998). Further details on Hamkins ’ use of FBP may also be found in Antos et al. (2015), pp. 2468–2470.

  22. 22.

    See Buzaglo (2002). Hints of a conception of concept expansion and evolution in mathematics may also be found in Lakatos (1976), which is also discussed by Buzaglo in the work mentioned.

  23. 23.

    However, Buzaglo does not deny that realism about concepts may be compatible with concept change and evolution. See Buzaglo (2002), pp. 116–137, where the author examines Gödel ’s realist conception which, contrary to what has been stated above, takes concept evolution precisely as proof that concepts are objective constructs.

  24. 24.

    H(κ), for a cardinal κ, is the collection of all sets whose cardinality is hereditarily less than κ, that is, all sets whose elements and the elements of whose elements and so on, have cardinality less than κ.

  25. 25.

    Bagaria et al. (2006) is a comprehensive introduction to Ω-logic .

  26. 26.

    Ω-logic makes its first appearance in Woodin (1999), and figures as a prominent tool in Woodin (2001). In those works, there is no direct reference to the set-generic multiverse , although the basic definitional ideas and concepts relating to it are already there.

  27. 27.

    A rather accessible treatment of the provability relation in Ω-logic , and of universally Baire sets, is in Woodin (2011), p. 108.

  28. 28.

    Moreover, Woodin was able to prove that:

    Theorem 3 (WoodinWoodin)

    ZFC+(⋆) ⊢Ω “H(ω 2)⊧¬CH”.

    It should be noted that the result requires the assumption of the existence of class-many Woodin cardinals, a particular strand of large cardinals having, as is known, far-reaching connections with Definable Determinacy Axioms, such as PD.

  29. 29.

    See Hamkins (2012), p. 430.

  30. 30.

    See, for instance, Viale (2016).

  31. 31.

    See Footnote 8.

  32. 32.

    Further details on all the different maximality principles explored by the HP may be found in Friedman (2016).

  33. 33.

    Of course, the fact that L is ‘minimal’ is simply a mathematical fact (insofar as L is the smallest inner model of V ). As is widely known, the view that construes L as a ‘minimality principle’ has been expressed by Gödel in (1947), p. 478–9. In that work, Gödel explicitly contrasts V = L to maximum principles. Maddy herself, as is known, has argued in favour of the claim that V = L would be ‘restrictive’. The full argument may be found in Maddy (1997), pp. 216–232.

  34. 34.

    This leads Hamkins to even surmise that: ‘For all we know, our entire current universe, large cardinals and all, is a countable transitive model inside a much larger model of V = L .’ (Hamkins 2012, p. 436).

  35. 35.

    It is true, however, that this goal was not fully attained, arguably, until (Zermelo 1930). Of course, another prioritary goal of the axiomatisation was to prevent the formation of the paradoxes, something which Zermelo carried out through introducing the Axiom of Separation already in Zermelo (1908). For this and other aspects of the history of the axiomatisation of set theory , see Ferreirós (2010), in particular, pp. 297–324.

  36. 36.

    At least, until first-order logic largely took over as a consequence, in particular, of Skolem ’s and Gödel ’s work. An exhaustive history of the triumph of first-order languages is provided by Shapiro in (1991), pp. 173–197. The relevance of ‘categoricity arguments’ for the ‘triumph’ of the single universe conception is also addressed in the same work, on pp. 250–259. A historically accurate reconstruction of the ‘first-order proposal’ for set theory is in Ferreirós (2010), pp. 357–64.

  37. 37.

    Of course this does not prevent one from interpreting Zermelo ’s conception of V  in multiversist terms. See, again, Footnote 8.

  38. 38.

    Although Skolemian relativism is a much stronger claim than this: it is the claim that set-theoretic concepts have no definite theory-independent meaning. Here, we cannot delve into the issue of whether Hamkins ’ FBP, ultimately, fosters such a form of anti-objectivism, as, for instance attributed by Field to Balaguer’s FBP in Field (2001), pp. 334–5.

  39. 39.

    In Steel’s notation, M G is the set-generic multiverse containing all worlds satisfying MV.

  40. 40.

    However, it might still be the case that there are ‘traces’ of CH in MV , if one accepts additional hypotheses, such as the existence of a core, which is described later on, p. 22. See also Footnote 41.

  41. 41.

    The Axiom says that V=HODM, where HOD is the class of all hereditarily definable sets, and M is a model of AD. Moreover, among other things, the axiom also implies CH. See Steel (2014), p. 171–177.

  42. 42.

    Ternullo also uses the term ‘Generous Arena’ for a different idea (Ternullo 2019, pp. 63–64), but in the passage under discussion here, he’s concerned with the sense delineated in my contribution to this volume.

  43. 43.

    See §I of [2017] for a bit more detail.

  44. 44.

    I use this term in place of Ternullo’s ‘ontological multiversism’ to leave room for a position that replaces objective entities with determinate truth values.

  45. 45.

    Steel (2014) and Woodin (2011) both take ZFC to be true in every world of the multiverse, but Hamkins sometimes does not: ‘There seems to be no reason to restrict inclusion only to ZFC models, as we can include models of weaker theories ZF, ZF, KP, and so on, perhaps even down to second-order number theory’ (Hamkins 2012, p. 436). On the other hand, we’ve seen that he addresses the foundational goal like this: ‘we expect to find all our familiar mathematical objects … inside any one of the universes of the multiverse’ (ibid., p. 419), which would seem to require at least ZFC (and if Risk Assessment is taken into account, large cardinals would be handy as well). In any case, Hamkins certainly embraces a number of objective truths (‘multiverse axioms’) about the multiverse in §9 of his [2012].

  46. 46.

    See [2011], pp. 55–59. In that book, I propose an alternative metaphysical position, Thin Realism, that avoids this problem by essentially reading its ontology off the analysis of proper methods, including extrinsic methods, but I doubt this is what Hamkins or Koellner or Ternullo has in mind.

  47. 47.

    We could think of this as the project of forming an optimally effective concept of set. Cf. the Arealism of [2011].

  48. 48.

    See [2011], pp. 131–137.

  49. 49.

    Something like this actually happened when the intuitive picture of sets as extensions of properties fell out of favor in light of its conflict with the extremely fruitful axiom of choice.

  50. 50.

    Ternullo contrasts ‘heuristic’ with ‘instrumental’ (2019, p. 53). See §III below.

  51. 51.

    Toby Meadows and I hope to clarify some of these matters in ‘A philosophical reconstruction of Steel’s multiverse’, in preparation. I also neglect the hyperuniverse program, simply because I don’t understand it well enough to comment.

  52. 52.

    To be clear, Ternullo isn’t claiming that the historical Zermelo understood his work in multiverse terms (see Ternullo 2019, p. 47, footnote 8). He holds, rather, that Zermelo is a ‘height potentialist’ and that this position can be seen as a kind of ‘height multiversism’ (see Footnote 13 below).

  53. 53.

    He leaves out the axiom of infinity to allow for a ‘finitary’ normal domain acceptable to intuitionists (so for him ω is a boundary number). As he sees it, a generous store of normal domains makes set theory adaptable for a wide range of applications.

  54. 54.

    Many observers see Zermelo as a potentialist, but I have my doubts. Though everyone, actualist and potentialist alike, uses a familiar range of metaphors – the universe is unending, etc. – it seems to me that the cash value of potentialism is the rejection of quantification over all sets. But this is exactly what Zermelo seems to do, for example, in arguing that there’s an inaccessible for every ordinal.

References

  • Antos, C., Friedman, S.-D., Honzik, R., & Ternullo, C. (2015). Multiverse conceptions in set theory. Synthese, 192(8), 2463–2488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrigoni, T., & Friedman, S. (2013). The hyperuniverse program. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 19(1), 77–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bagaria, J., Castells, N., & Larson, P. (2006). An Omega-logic primer. In J. Bagaria & S. Todorcevic (Eds.), Set theory (Trends in mathematics, pp. 1–28). Basel: Birkhäuser.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balaguer, M. (1995). A platonist epistemology. Synthese, 103, 303–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balaguer, M. (1998). Platonism and anti-platonism in mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boolos, G. (1971). The iterative conception of set. Journal of Philosophy, 68(8), 215–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buzaglo, M. (2002). The logic of concept expansion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferreirós, J. (2010). Labyrinth of thought. A history of set theory and its role in modern mathematics. Basel: Birkhäuser.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2001). Truth and absence of fact. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, S. (2016). Evidence for set-theoretic truth and the hyperuniverse programme. IfCoLog Journal of Logics and their Applications, 3(4), 517–555.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gödel, K. (1947). What is Cantor’s continuum problem? American Mathematical Monthly, 54, 515–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamkins, J. D. (2012). The set-theoretic multiverse. Review of Symbolic Logic, 5(3), 416–449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koellner, P. (2009). On reflection principles. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 157(2–3), 206–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koellner, P. (2014). Large cardinals and determinacy. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/large-cardinals-determinacy/

  • Lakatos, I. (1976). Proofs and refutations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Linnebo, Ø. (2013). The potential hierarchy of sets. Review of Symbolic Logic, 6(2), 205–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (1996). Set-theoretic naturalism. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 61(2), 490–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (1997). Naturalism in mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (2007). Second philosophy: A naturalistic method. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (2011). Defending the axioms. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (2017). Set-theoretic foundations. In A. Caicedo, J. Cummings, P. Koellner, & P. B. Larson (Eds.), Foundations of mathematics. Essays in Honor of W. Hugh Woodin’s 60th Birthday (Contemporary mathematics, Vol. 690, pp. 289–322). Providence: American Mathematical Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, D. (2001). Multiple universes of sets and indeterminate truth values. Topoi, 20, 5–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paseau, A. (2016). Naturalism in the philosophy of mathematics. In M. Leng (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (1991). Foundations without foundationalism. A case for second-order logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelah, S. (2003). Logical dreams. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 40(2), 203–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steel, J. (2014). Gödel’s program. In J. Kennedy (Ed.), Interpreting Gödel. Critical essays (pp. 153–179). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ternullo, C., & Friedman, S.-D. (2016). The search for new axioms in the hyperuniverse programme. In F. Boccuni & A. Sereni (Eds.), Philosophy of mathematics: Objectivity, realism and proof. Filmat studies in the philosophy of mathematics (Boston studies in philosophy of science, pp. 165–188). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Väänänen, J. (2014). Multiverse set theory and absolutely undecidable propositions. In J. Kennedy (Ed.), Interpreting Gödel. Critical essays (pp. 180–205). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Viale, M. (2016). Category forcings, MM+++ and generic absoluteness for the theory of strong forcing axioms. Journal of the American Mathematical Society, 29(3), 675–728.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, H. (1974). From mathematics to philosophy. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodin, W. H. (1999). The axiom of determinacy, forcing axioms and the non-stationary ideal. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Woodin, W. H. (2001). The continuum hypothesis. Notices of the American Mathematical Society, Part 1: 48(6), 567–576; Part 2: 48(7), 681–690.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodin, W. H. (2011). The realm of the infinite. In W. H. Woodin & M. Heller (Eds.), Infinity. New research frontiers (pp. 89–118). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zermelo, E. (1908). Investigations in the foundations of set theory. In J. van Heijenoort (Ed.), From frege to Gödel. A source book in mathematical logic, 1879–1931 (pp. 199–215). Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zermelo, E. (1930). Über Grenzzahlen und Mengenbereiche: neue Untersuchungen über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 16, 29–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

References to Reply to Ternullo on the Multiverse

Download references

Acknowledgement

I would like to thank the University of Tartu for its support through ASTRA project PER ASPERA (financed by the European Regional Development Fund).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Claudio Ternullo .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix: Reply to Ternullo on the Multiverse

Appendix: Reply to Ternullo on the Multiverse

Doctor Ternullo raises a host of important issues, but I focus here on the central theme: his defense of the multiverse from the point of view of a naturalist, indeed, a naturalist of a particular variety that I call a ‘second philosopher’. In a recent paper on the foundations of mathematics (a companion piece to my contribution to the present volume), I considered the possibility that some sort of multiverse theory could replace our current set theory in a range of foundational jobs now performed by ZFC + Large Cardinals (LCs). I concluded that for now, in the current state of knowledge, it isn’t clear that this move is feasible or advisable. Ternullo apparently disputes this conclusion: ‘the multiverse may be as acceptable as the universe for … the foundational purposes of set theory’ (Ternullo 2019, p. 46).

In an odd twist, though, Ternullo argues that one fundamental aspect of the foundational goal, the job I call Generous Arena,Footnote 42 is itself misguided, that the argument for it is, for my naturalist, ‘slightly embarrassing’ (Ternullo 2019, p. 63). As it happens, leading multiverse theorists don’t see the situation this way; they embrace this foundational goal and argue that their theories meet it. For example, this from Hamkins:

The multiverse view does not abandon the goal of using set theory as an epistemological and ontological foundation for mathematics, for we expect to find all our familiar mathematical objects … inside any one of the universes of the multiverse. (Hamkins 2012, p. 419)

And here’s Steel:

We want one framework theory [i.e., foundational theory], to be used by all, so that we can use each other’s work. It is better for all our flowers to bloom in the same garden. If truly distinct frameworks emerged, the first order of business would be to unify them. … The goal of our framework theory is to maximize interpretive power, to provide a language and theory in which all mathematics, of today and of the future so far as we can anticipate it, can be developed. (Steel 2014, pp. 164–165)

Ternullo seems to reject this approach, on the grounds that the argument for the foundational goal itself is flawed (Ternullo 2019, pp. 61–63).

That argument, as he sees it, rests on the claim that Generous Arena was present early on in the history of set theory – as it was – and that this temporal priority implies logical priority. I think we can all agree that this is a weak argument, but it’s not the right argument, as I hope is clear from §I of my contribution here.Footnote 43 Regardless of when they first arose, the mathematical attractions of Generous Arena, along with Risk Assessment, Metamathematical Corral, and Shared Standard, remain as strong today as ever. In his willingness to forgo Generous Arena, Ternullo sounds a theme familiar, as we’ve seen, in category-theoretic and univalent foundations, but not one we hear from multiverse theorists like Hamkins and Steel. This creates some mismatch in the debate between Ternullo and me, since my analysis is explicitly addressed to the question of the multiverse’s aptitude for filling this foundational role (among others) and he seems to think it needn’t be filled. Still, there are some surrounding points well worth considering.

I begin, as Ternullo does, by attending to various versions of multiversism, though now with an eye not to the mathematical differences between them, but to the different philosophical or methodological stances one might take toward them. §II sketches my concerns about the multiverse in a foundational role, and §III considers other significant roles that multiverse thinking might play.

1.1 I. What Is a Multiverse View?

Ternullo begins with a straightforward characterization of the central distinction:

Whether set theory should be interpreted as the theory of a single universe of sets … or … as a theory about multiple structures … that is, about a set theoretic ‘multiverse’. (Ternullo 2019, p. 43)

He alludes to Koellner’s distinction between pluralism and non-pluralism:

pluralism … maintains that … although there are practical reasons that one might give in favor of one set of axioms over another – say, that it is more useful for a given task –, there are no theoretical reasons that can be given …

non-pluralism … maintains that the independence results merely indicate the paucity of our standard resources for justifying mathematical statements. … theoretical reasons can be given for new axioms. (Koellner 2014, p. 1)

Multiversism, then, is a model-theoretic version of pluralism:

There is not a single universe of set theory but rather a multiverse of legitimate candidates, some of which may be preferable to others for certain practical purposes, but none of which can be said to be the ‘true’ universe. (Koellner 2013, p. 3)

Ternullo agrees that multiversism is ‘an ontological (semantic) variant’ of pluralism (Ternullo 2019, p. 44). Presumably he also takes his multiversist to hold that, though there might be practical reasons for preferring one truth value for an indeterminate statement over another or one universe of the multiverse over another, there are no theoretical reasons for this – there is no determinate truth value, no ‘true’ universe.

Now Ternullo notes that unabashedly metaphysical views like these may be problematic for the naturalist, but he concludes that the metaphysics can be disregarded (Ternullo 2019, §4.1). He has his own reasons for saying this, but in any case, we agree on the underlying point, that metaphysics is largely irrelevant to the mathematical issues at hand. In the hope of clarifying some of these matters, let me sketch a rough taxonomy of philosophical stances on multiversism, beginning from the most ontologically or semantically loaded and moving on from there.

On the deeply metaphysical end of the spectrum, there’s Hamkins’s position:

With forcing, we seem to have discovered the existence of other mathematical universes, outside our own universe, and the multiverse view asserts that yes, indeed, this is the case. (Hamkins 2012, p. 425) Each … universe exists independently in the same Platonic sense that proponents of the universe view regard their universe to exist. (Ibid., pp. 416–417)

In Koellner’s terms, presumably this Metaphysical MultiversismFootnote 44 takes ‘theoretical’ considerations to tell us something about the structure of its generous ontology, perhaps, for example, that every world thinks ZFC.Footnote 45 It might seem that the theoretical/practical distinction coincides with the intrinsic/extrinsic distinction familiar in the philosophical foundations of set theory – where intrinsic considerations are somehow intuitive, or self-evident, or contained in the concept of set, and extrinsic considerations involve attractive consequences or interrelations or something of that sort – but I think this can’t be right. Koellner writes that …

given the current state of our knowledge a case can be made for being a non – pluralist about ZFC and large cardinal axioms (Koellner 2013, p. 4)

… in other words, in multiverse terms, for assuming these axioms across all worlds of the multiverse, and from his other writings, it’s clear that some of this case is extrinsic. Similarly, Hamkins allows that

the mathematician’s measure of a philosophical position may be the value of the mathematics to which it leads (Hamkins 2012, p. 440).

So it appears that at least some extrinsic considerations must also yield information about the multiverse, must also be included under ‘theoretical’.

Suppose, then, that a certain set-theoretic statement, perhaps a candidate for a new axiom to be true in all worlds, or perhaps another sort of general claim about the structure of the multiverse, has many mathematical advantages and no mathematical disadvantages. This wouldn’t be enough for the Metaphysical Multiversist to endorse it, because we’d have to be confident that those mathematical merits produce theoretical support, not mere practical support. We’d have to be confident that our belief in that set-theoretic statement, however attractive it might be, isn’t just wishful thinking, that the objective mathematical realm of the multiverse doesn’t just happen to deny us something we’d very much like to have. Many philosophers, in the tradition of Benacerraf’s famous challenge to Platonism, would ask how we could come to know that our beliefs are tracking the truth about an abstract realm. My naturalist asks a question that’s logically prior to Benacerraf’s: why should we demand more than mathematical merits? Why should those mathematical merits be held hostage to extra-mathematical metaphysics? Her answer is that this is wrong-headed, that the compelling mathematical reasons should be enough all by themselves.Footnote 46

Though Metaphysical Multiversism is uncongenial to the naturalist, as Ternullo says, this isn’t the end of the story; there are other varieties of multiversism. We could, for example, leave metaphysics aside and simply talk about theories. Set theory, then, isn’t the project of describing an abstract mathematical realm; it’s the project of forging a powerful mathematical theory to serve the foundation goal (among others).Footnote 47 The universist advocates ZFC and its extensions in this role; the multiversist proposes an alternative multiverse theory of sets and worlds to take its place. For these purposes, all extrinsic considerations would be on equal footing; there’d be no distinction between ‘theoretical’ or truth-tracking cases and ‘merely practical’ cases. This Theory Multiversism is an option entirely open to the naturalist, should the evidence point that way.

A final variant sees the multiverse as analogous, not to a universe ontology, not to a universe theory, but to the iterative conception. In universe thinking, the iterative conception serves as an intuitive picture that helps us see our way around in deriving consequences from the axioms or seeking new avenues for axiom choice. From the naturalist’s non-metaphysical perspective, intrinsic considerations based on this picture are potentially of great heuristic value; the history of the subject amply demonstrates what an immensely successful tool the iterative conception has been. But, for the naturalist, it’s important to stress that the value of this intuitive picture rests on the great mathematical merits of the work it’s inspired, in other words, on its extrinsic success.Footnote 48 If we were presented with an alternative intuitive picture that conceptualizes set-theory differently, if that alternative way of guiding the subject were more fruitful than the iterative conception, we should switch our allegiance without regret.Footnote 49 The Heuristic MultiversistFootnote 50 argues that the intuitive picture of a multiverse is just such an alternative; he might propose that ZFC and its extensions, guided by the iterative conception, should be replaced with a multiverse theory based on the new picture. This would be a version of Theory Multiversism, but other possibilities emerge in §III below. Either way, the basic suggestion is that the intuitive multiverse picture would guide the practice in new and different directions with important mathematical advantages.

There are no doubt other ways to frame a philosophical perspective for multiversism, and perhaps predictably, one prominent multiverse theory, the one due to Steel, doesn’t fit squarely in any of the three bins just described. As Ternullo notes, Steel is out to explore whether CH is ‘meaningful’; his multiverse theory is intended, not as an alternative subject matter (Metaphysical Multiversism), not exactly as an alternative theory (Theory Multiversism), but as a way of determining which, if any, sentences in the language of set theory (not the multiverse language of sets and worlds) are ‘meaningless’, pose ‘pseudo-questions’. How he goes about this and what conclusions he draws are quite subtle matters that go well beyond the scope of this reply.Footnote 51 Still, I hope these three rough categories will help illuminate the debate between Ternullo and me. As this is an intramural debate between naturalists, we’re focused primarily on multiversisms of the Theory and Heuristic varieties.

1.2 II. Naturalistic Concerns About Multiversism

In the paper Ternullo is discussing, I raise a number of questions about multiverse theories as potential alternatives to ZFC and its extensions as our basic foundational theory. The most fundamental of these is that a foundational theory, as we now understand it, has to be a theory, has to be an explicit set of axioms capable of doing the foundational jobs. Of the multiverse accounts on offer, only Steel’s comes with a set of axioms, a fully explicit first-order theory of sets and worlds, but as noted, his goal is to evaluate the sentences of ordinary set theory, not to replace them with something different. So, flat-footed as it sounds, the general lack of an explicit multiverse theory strikes me as a serious obstacle to a new and different multiverse foundation.

Hamkins’s stand on the foundational status of the multiverse was quoted above:

We expect to find all our familiar mathematical objects … inside any one of the universes of the multiverse. (Hamkins 2012, p. 419)

Roughly speaking, it seems any world of the multiverse can serve as our Generous Arena, and ZFC (satisfied by that world) as our Shared Standard. Presumably Risk Assessment is to be carried out in a world with large cardinals, that is, in ZFC+LCs. There’s some question about Meta-mathematical Corral: if we only care about corralling a generous arena, we’re once again thrown back on ZFC and its extensions; if we want to corral all of mathematics, it seems we’d need a theory of our multiverse, which we’ve seen Hamkins’s doesn’t provide. On Steel’s view, ZFC+LCs turns up in the meaningful part of set-theoretic language and continues to carry out its usual foundational functions. For the most part, then, ZFC and its extensions retain their foundational roles – in that respect, no alternative is actually on offer. So it’s hard to see a case for replacing a universe view with multiverse view for foundational purposes.

But this isn’t the end of the story. Some version of the multiverse perspective may have such attractive mathematical features that we’re moved to adopt it even if a familiar theory like ZFC remains our official foundation. Ternullo mounts a case along these lines.

1.3 III. Ternullo’s Defense

One striking turn in Ternullo’s discussion is his characterization of Zermelo’s famous ‘On boundary numbers and domains of sets’ (Zermelo 1930) as ‘the first description of a multiverse’ (Ternullo 2019, p. 47).Footnote 52 If this were so, it would go a long way toward showing that multiversism has important and far-reaching mathematical consequences! Working in a strong implicit meta-theory, Zermelo presents an analysis of ‘normal domains’ characterized by second-order ZFC minus InfinityFootnote 53: their ‘boundary numbers’ are inaccessible cardinals; they can be decomposed into ranks up to that number (this is touted as one of the extrinsic benefits of Foundation); any two with the same boundary number are isomorphic; for any two with different boundary numbers, one is an initial segment of the other. The question then arises: are there any normal domains, are there any boundary numbers? Zermelo mounts an argument in the meta-theory that for any ordinal α, there’s a corresponding boundary number κ α; in modern terms, he’s argued for the Axiom of Inaccessibles:

We must postulate the existence of an unlimited sequence of boundary numbers as a new axiom for the ‘meta-theory of sets’. (Zermelo 1930, p. 429)

Though Zermelo does take second-order ‘ZFC-Infinity’ to characterize each of an unending series of normal domains, I see no evidence that he intends his second-order ‘ZFC + a proper class of inaccessibles’ in the meta-theory as anything other than a description of the single universe in which all these normal domains reside.Footnote 54 If including an axiom of inaccessibles is enough to qualify a list of axioms as a multiverse theory, then almost all set theorists these days are multiversists; this sets the bar far too low, renders the term useless. So it seems that Zermelo is best left out of this discussion.

Ternullo is on stronger ground when he extends the appeal to mathematical consequences into contemporary set theory. I’m happy to grant that, for example, Hamkins’s multiverse thinking has led to a fruitful investigation of ‘set-theoretic geology’ or that Steel’s approach has focused attention on important questions about the ‘core’. Cases like these display a clear heuristic benefit to thinking in terms of an intuitive multiverse picture – on this Ternullo and I agree – but he goes on to insist that these benefits aren’t purely heuristic, that they are actually ‘instrumental’. He draws this distinction from a question raised in my paper: can all the welcome mathematics inspired by multiverse thinking be carried out in our familiar universe theory, that is, are these all theorems of ZFC and its extensions? If the answer to this question is no, then multiverse thinking would be more than merely heuristic – fully instrumental, in Ternullo’s terms – but as far as I can tell, the answer is yes, which Ternullo seems to acknowledge:

It has been made clear that there may be no specific task that the universist may not try to successfully emulate within their single V. However, it is, in my view, rather apparent that the multiverse enormously facilitates fundamental practical tasks. (Ternullo 2019, p. 66)

This is just to say that multiverse thinking is of great (purely) heuristic value.

Notice that we have here instances of Heuristic Multiversism different from what was envisioned in §I: the multiverse picture isn’t being used to inspire new axioms toward a version of Theory Multiversism, but to inspire new mathematics, new concepts and methods, within our existing theory of ZFC and its extensions. And there’s another potential contribution of Heuristic Multiversism, as well. Hamkins observes that

There is no reason to consider all universes in the multiverse equally, and we may simply be more interested in parts of the multiverse consisting of universes satisfying very strong theories, such as ZFC plus large cardinals. (Hamkins 2012, p. 436)

Now the process of narrowing down to a restricted range of worlds may well be functionally equivalent to the process of adding new axioms to ZFC, so what’s of interest here is the suggestion that thinking in multiverse terms could bring new and different considerations to bear on that process. In other words, multiverse thinking might help us to refine our official theory of sets. In fact, this may be the ultimate upshot of Steel’s line of thought: a stretch of multiverse thinking leads him to propose a new axiom for ordinary set theory.

In sum, then, our naturalist has no straightforward form of Theory Multiversism, only Steel’s set of axioms with a different motivation, but there seems to be ample room for Heuristic Multiversism to do significant mathematical work in a number of different ways. We can draw two morals. The first is that ZFC and its extensions aren’t uniquely tied to the intuitive universe picture of the iterative conception. They could be thought of, instead, as the shared theory of a range of worlds in the multiverse, so that what the universist sees as adding new axioms about V, could instead be seen as a narrowing of the range of worlds we take to be of interest. The second moral is one that should appeal to Ternullo’s naturalism: since these intuitive pictures, universist and multiversist, are playing a merely heuristic role, there’s no reason at all not to exploit them both, no reason at all not to switch back and forth depending on which is more suggestive in a given context. In the end, set theorists should feel entirely free to think in any intuitive terms that can lead them to good mathematics!

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Ternullo, C. (2019). Maddy On The Multiverse. In: Centrone, S., Kant, D., Sarikaya, D. (eds) Reflections on the Foundations of Mathematics. Synthese Library, vol 407. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-15655-8_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics