Skip to main content
Log in

Identity, incarnation, and the imago Dei

  • Article
  • Published:
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A number of thinkers suggest that, given certain conditions, it’s possible that any concrete human nature could have been united hypostatically to the second Person of the Trinity. Oliver Crisp argues that a potency to have been possibly hypostatically united to the Logos is an important part of what it means for a human person to be made in the image of God. Against this line of reasoning, and building on an argument in print by Andrew Jaeger, I argue two things: first, that many metaphysics of human persons on offer fail to allow the Logos possibly to unite hypostatically to just any concrete human nature. And this is because, given the necessity of identity (if x = y, necessarily x = y), every metaphysics that deploys an identity relation between a human person and her human nature or some essential component of her human nature fails to allow concrete human natures to be identical to any other person than they in fact are or else to lack some essential component that is identical to any other person than it in fact is. And, in the Incarnation, the Logos does not unite with a person. Second, supposing the preceding line of reasoning goes through, I argue that Oliver Crisp’s thesis about the imago Dei is mistaken, provided that it relies on a metaphysics of human persons that deploys an identity relation between a person and her concrete human nature or else some essential component of her concrete human nature.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Cf. (Flint 2011, 192; Flint 2009; Pawl 2016, 65–67; Crisp 2016, 63; Crisp 2007, 83). Aquinas appears even to endorse a view consistent with this. Cf. (Aquinas 1952b, III.Q4.a.2, ad.3).

  2. I set aside discussion of the sort of constitution metaphysics deployed by Lynne Rudder Baker, et al. I do so because I find those views to be shot through with philosophical problems, which would be the subject of an entirely separate paper. I’ve discussed her view in (Turner 2014). For Baker’s constitution view see, among others, (Baker 1999, 2000, 2002, 2005, 2007a, b). See also (Corcoran 1999). For various arguments against constitution metaphysics see, among others, (Turner 2014; Olson 1999, 2001).

  3. This is quoted verbatim from (Jaeger 2017, 147). I have refrained from using quotation marks in this instance for style purposes. Note that this is Jaeger’s principle; it’s a principle that is stronger than the standard necessity of identity, viz., if x = y, then necessarily, x = y. A referee worries that this stronger principle might not be true; or else that I need to defend this (NI) claim. Now, (NI) isn’t mine; dialectically I have no stake in whether it’s true or false. But, for argument, I assume that it is true. In Jaeger’s defense, I take it that he assumes that the stronger principle, (NI), is true because of S5. For, if x is possibly necessarily identical to y, then necessarily x is identical to y. The clumsiness of this way of phrasing (NI) is, of course, an example of why S5 is popular in modal logic. For one thing, if identity is a necessary relation, then “necessarily identical” is redundant; for another, on S5, possibly necessary entails necessary. For a defense of S5, it’s helpful to start with (Garson 2018). But none of this need detain us. For, the arguments that follow in this paper assume the logic granted by the dialectic into which I’m stepping. Jaeger’s (NI) might be false. My main aim in this paper isn’t to render a verdict on this matter. It’s to show, instead, what else follows from Jaeger’s already published argument. In any case, I trust that those parties involved in this literature accept (NI) and S5 modal logic. I confirmed this with Oliver Crisp, for example, in personal conversation.

  4. Brian Leftow (2002) argues that there’s a symmetry between the abstract-nature view of the incarnation and concrete-nature view, such that one only occurs if the other does. But, he suggests, the concrete nature view is basic because the abstract nature view occurs only “by concrete nature incarnation” (278–279).

  5. (OP) borrows from Jaeger, though he does not call it “One Person (OP)” and (OP) specifies things not spelled out in Jaeger. But I take it that this is consistent with what he means. I follow him too in thinking that this is affirmed in Anathema 4 of Constantinople II (the Fifth Ecumenical Council). See Jaeger (2017, 147).

  6. I’ll not offer and theories about how the Incarnation works or how the Logos could become human. I leave that for others.

  7. Thanks to Jordan Wessling and Oliver Crisp for highlighting this point on an earlier draft.

  8. Again, this is verbatim; but I’ve dropped the quotation marks for style.

  9. For purposes of this paper, assume that I hold the (rather common) theological axiom that the Incarnate Logos is not a human person; rather, He’s a divine person with a human nature. If that’s correct—a position, again, I assume for this paper—then ‘person’ in (IV) does not, and cannot, refer to the Logos. (IV) concerns persons who are human persons.

  10. Thanks to Ryan Mullins for this turn of phrase in personal correspondence.

  11. This ended up ruling out the Alexandrian—even Apollinarian—“Logos-sarx” view. Cf. (Pannenberg 1968, 288; Grillmeier 1987, 101–102). But as Crisp (2007, 38 note 7) notes, things may have been a little more complex than this. Apollinarius may have affirmed the presence of a soul distinct from the Logos in the human nature of Christ. If so, he denied that Christ’s human soul had a mind and will distinct from the Logos; thus the Logos took the place of the mind and will in the soul of Christ.

  12. There may well be other theological problems with this generic souls view of the Incarnation, too. See (Crisp 2007, 53ff) for a helpful discussion.

  13. Again, I leave discussion of Baker-style constitution metaphysics aside. Again, this view is one I’ve tackled in (Turner 2014).

  14. I borrow this analogy from an anonymous reviewer who read a previous draft of this essay.

  15. By a “natural kind” I mean something synonymous to what Lynne Rudder Baker (1999, 2002, 2007a, b) calls a “primary kind,” wherein a “primary kind” or “natural kind” is a substance sortal marking the distinctions between kinds of substances by their respective essential properties. “Natural kind” has been used this way elsewhere in the literature. See, for example, Brown (2005, 169ff). Other similar uses of the term “natural kind” appear in the work of Moreland and Rae (2000, 73ff), Rosenkrantz (2012), Brower (2012), Wiggins (1976), and others.

  16. According Pawl’s analysis, persons aren’t even kinds of supposits/hypostases. Rather, persons are accidents predicated of supposits/hypostases. Here I confess mild confusion as to how Pawl thinks of a hypostasis/supposit. For he suggests that “X is a supposit (hypostasis) if and only if x is a complete being, incommunicable by identity, not apt to inhere in anything, and not sustained by anything” (Pawl 2016, 32). This, though, is exactly how I understand a substance. In other words, these necessary and sufficient conditions read to me as follows: “X is a hypostasis if and only if it’s a substance.” It’s not clear to me whether Pawl means that a hypostasis is a particular kind of substance or if it’s just another name for a substance. For the purposes of this paper, I take it that substance/hypostasis/supposit can be used interchangeably. The important point is that, on Pawl’s view (and Flint’s, in so far as he offers a thesis like (AT*)), person is neither a kind of hypostasis nor a kind of substance; it’s an accident predicated of a hypostasis/substance, a contingent way in which a particular hypostasis/substance exists. I leave aside whether Flint or Pawl are, in fact, committed to a view like (AT*). Christopher Brown (2005, 168ff) suggests, too, that Aquinas might categorize natural kinds as a substance sortal as opposed to a phase sortal. What Flint and Pawl provide, though, and to which I’m offering my criticism, is that “being a person” is a phase-sortal of a substance rather than a kind of substance.

  17. I note here that it seems to me that these Flintian/Pawline (not to be confused with Pauline!) views are consistent with Baker-style constitution accounts. But see note 2. Thanks to Jordan Wessling who provided some important feedback to help me clarify this point.

  18. Jaeger (2017, 148) likewise deploys this sort of reasoning about the Incarnation.

  19. An anonymous referee wonders if Crisp has in mind a kind of “fitness” for hypostatic union latent in individual human natures rather than a “probability” for an individual human’s hypostatic union. Here the referee points to Thomas Aquinas’s explication of “fitness” vis-à-vis a human nature’s being assumed by the Logos in the Incarnation in (Aquinas 1952a, III.Q4.a1). Here I confess mild confusion as to the nature of Thomas’s argument in this Question. But, whatever it is, suppose Crisp has it in mind. If so, I cannot see how it gets around my worries provided that Crisp holds an (IV) understanding of human persons. For, if Crisp affirms (IV) and that hypostatic union just is a relation that results only in one person, my arguments imply that the hypostatic union of another concrete nature to the Logos other than the one he in fact has is impossible. I am not at all sure what it would mean to say that a substance, S, has a fitness for some relation, R, and that R isn’t a possible relation for S. See the lines of reasoning leading up to note 7 of this article.

  20. Pace (Mullins 2015, 6) and (Mullins 2017, 522).

  21. By “historically were generated” I mean, generated by Church Fathers when attempting to clarify orthodox Christology. There is some debate, however, whether any such clear distinctions were in the writings of the Fathers. For competing views see, for example, (Crisp 2007, 73 note 2; Mullins 2015, 6; Flint 2016, 185–187; Shults 1996; Lang 1998). Ivor Davidson thinks that one can begin to see such distinctions assumed by Cyril of Alexandria and the council at Chalcedon (which framed the so-called Definition of Chalcedon in 451). See (Davidson 2001, 139–140).

  22. I assume, without argument, the traditional claim that the Apostle Paul wrote the Letter to the Colossians. Nothing of any importance (in this paper, anyway) rides on this.

  23. My insert.

  24. For some recent exegetes advancing this view, see (Middleton 2014, 45ff; Middleton 2005, 89ff; Beale 2004, 68ff; Walton 2015, 104–127; Enns 2012, 72ff). For at least one systematician sensitive to this understanding of the imago Dei, see (Fergusson 2007, 74–75). Here I take the points of Joshua Farris and Oliver Crisp, both of whom are wont to argue that the functions of the image bearer presuppose a particular kind of ontology. In which case, literature supposing that ontological notions of the imago Dei are mutually exclusive of functional notions (or relational notions) is mistaken (Farris 2017, 35; Crisp 2016, 59–60). I agree with this shared insight.

  25. For one exhaustive treatment, see (Beale 2004). See also (Walton 2009; Levenson 1984; Fretheim 1984, 37; Morales 2014).

  26. For some interesting discussion on what the texts mine mean when they say that the knowledge of God and His glory might fill the earth as the waters cover the sea, see (Levenson 1984, 289–290).

  27. This paper was researched and written in part while I worked on the Analytic Theology Project at Fuller Theological Seminary. This project was funded by The John Templeton Foundation. My thanks to my colleagues on the project who read various drafts of this essay: James Arcadi, Oliver Crisp, Jesse Gentile, Steven Nemes, Jordan Wessling, and Christopher Woznicki. My thanks also to Ryan Mullins and two anonymous referees for helpful comments on a previous draft of this essay.

References

  • Aquinas, St. T. (1952a). The summa theologica. Vol. 2 in Great books of the western world, no. 19, (R. M. Hutchins, Ed., Fathers of the English Dominican Province, Trans.). Chicago, IL: Encyclopedia Britannica.

  • Aquinas, St. T. (1952b). The summa theologica. Vol. 2 in Great books of the Western World, no. 20 (R. M. Hutchins, Ed., Fathers of the English Dominican Province, Trans.). Chicago, IL: Encyclopedia Britannica.

  • Baker, L. R. (1999). Unity without identity: A new look at material constitution. Midwest Studies in Philosophy,23(1), 144–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, L. R. (2000). Persons and bodies: A constitution view. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, L. R. (2002). The ontological status of persons. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,62(2), 370–388.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, L. R. (2005). Death and afterlife. In W. J. Wainwright (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, L. R. (2007a). Persons and the metaphysics of resurrection. Religious Studies,43(3), 333–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, L. R. (2007b). The metaphysics of everyday life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beale, G. K. (2004). The temple and the church’s mission. Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boethius. n.d. Treatise against eutyches and nestorius. In The theological tractates (E. Capps, T. E. Page, & W. H. D. Rouse, Ed., H. F. Stewart & E. K. Rand, Trans.) Christian classics ethereal library. http://www.ccel.org/boethius/tracts.pdf.

  • Brower, J. E. (2012). Matter, form, and individuation. In B. Davies & E. Stump (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, C. M. (2005). Aquinas and the ship of theseus. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corcoran, K. (1999). Persons, bodies, and the constitution relation. Southern Journal of Philosophy,37, 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, O. D. (2007). Divinity and humanity: The incarnation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, O. D. (2009). God incarnate: Explorations in christology. London: T&T Clark.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, O. D. (2016). The word enfleshed. Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, I. (2001). Theologizing the human Jesus: An ancient (and modern) approach to christology reassessed. International Journal of Systematic Theology,3(2), 139–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enns, P. (2012). The evolution of Adam. Grand Rapids, MI: Brazos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farris, J. R. (2017). The soul of theological anthropology: A cartesian exploration. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fergusson, D. (2007). Creation. In J. Webster, K. Tanner, & I. Torrance (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of systematic theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flint, T. P. (2009). The possibilities of incarnation: Some radical molinist suggestions. In O. D. Crisp (Ed.), A reader in contemporary philosophical theology. London: T&T Clark.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flint, T. P. (2011). Molinism and the incarnation. In K. Perszyk (Ed.), Molinism: The contemporary debate. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flint, T. P. (2016). Orthodoxy and incarnation: A reply to Mullins. Journal of Analytic Theology,4, 185–187.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fretheim, T. E. (1984). The suffering of God: An old testament perspective. Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2018). Modal logic. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Fall 2018 edition (N. Z.Edward Ed.) https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/logic-modal/.

  • Grillmeier, A. (1987). Christ in christian tradition, Vol. 2: From the council of chalcedon (451) to gregory the great (590604), (P. Allen & J. Cawte, Trans.). London: A. R. Mowbray and Co. Ltd.

  • Jaeger, A. (2017). Hylemorphic animalism and the incarnational problem of identity. Journal of Analytic Theology,5, 145–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lang, U. M. (1998). Anhypostatos–enhypostatos: Church fathers, protestant orthodoxy and Karl Barth. The Journal of Theological Studies,49(2), 630–657.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leftow, B. (2002). A timeless God incarnate. In S. T. Davis, D. Kendall, & G. O’Collins (Eds.), The incarnation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levenson, J. D. (1984). The temple and the world. The Journal of Religion,64(3), 275–298.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDonough, S. M. (2017). Creation and new creation: understanding God’s creation project. Peabody, MA: Hendrickson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Middleton, J. R. (2005). The liberating image. Grand Rapids, MI: Brazos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Middleton, J. R. (2014). A new heaven and a new Earth. Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morales, L. M. (2014). Cult and cosmos: Tilting toward a temple-centered theology. Leuven, BE: Peeters.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreland, J. P., & Rae, Scott B. (2000). Body & soul: Human nature & the crisis in ethics. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mullins, R. T. (2015). Flint’s molinism and the incarnation is too radical. Journal of Analytic Theology,3, 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mullins, R. T. (2017). Flint’s ‘molinism and the incarnation’ is still too radical. Journal of Analytic Theology,5, 515–532.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, E. T. (1999). Reply to Lynne Baker. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,59(1), 161–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, E. T. (2001). Thinking animals and the constitution view. In Symposium on persons and bodies. A field guide to philosophy of mind. http://www.uniroma3.it/kant/field/bakersymp_olson.htm.

  • Pannenberg, W. (1968). JesusGod and man (Lewis L. W. & A. P. Duane, Trans.). London: SCM Press.

  • Pawl, T. (2016). In defense of conciliar christology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenkrantz, G. (2012). Ontological categories. In T. Tahko (Ed.), Contemporary aristotelian metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shults, F. L. (1996). A dubious christological formula: From Leontius of Byzantium to Karl Barth. Theological Studies,57(3), 431–446.

    Google Scholar 

  • Torrance, T. F. (2015). Incarnation: The person and life of Christ. Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, J. T., Jr. (2014). No explanation of persons, no explanation of resurrection: On Lynne Baker’s constitution view and the resurrection of human persons. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion,76(3), 297–317.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, J. H. (2009). The lost world of genesis one. Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, J. H. (2015). The lost world of Adam and Eve. Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, D. (1976). Locke, Butler, and the stream of consciousness: And men as a natural kind. In A. O. Rorty (Ed.), The identities of persons. Berkley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, N. T. (2012). How God became king. New York, NY: HarperOne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, N. T. (2015). Excursus. In J. H. Walton (Ed.), The lost world of Adam and Eve. Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to James T. Turner Jr..

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Turner, J.T. Identity, incarnation, and the imago Dei. Int J Philos Relig 88, 115–131 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-019-09716-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-019-09716-z

Keywords

Navigation