Skip to content
Publicly Available Published by De Gruyter March 14, 2023

Challenges of Transhumanism for Virtue Ethics

  • Michal Vivoda ORCID logo EMAIL logo
From the journal Human Affairs

Abstract

In this paper we consider some of the basic elements of virtue ethics in confrontation with selected ideas of representatives of trans- and post-humanism. Their ideas challenge us to re-justify and defend the uniqueness of man (the person) as a moral subject in his complex relational physical-psycho-spiritual unity. Using this holistic moral-anthropological vision, it is possible to justify the uniqueness of the human act as moral; the nature and significance of virtue as a moral disposition for a truly good and happy life; the nature and significance of happiness as a true complex eudaimonia in the dynamics of human development. In this complex process, technical artefacts and technologies help man to act in a truly human way towards himself and others, if he uses them rightly.

1 Introduction

Contemporary representatives of trans- and post-humanism pose challenges with their views and insights that invite moral philosophers to rethink, re-justify, and defend the basic moral elements. It is generally acknowledged that moral philosophy is concerned with moral action from the point of view of the acting subject (so-called ‘first-person’ ethics). This perspective is integral because the human being as doer is a complex relational physical-psycho-spiritual unity. From the point of view of ethical normativity, the moral philosopher asks: What ought I to be, i.e. what moral character ought I to acquire and develop in order to act correctly? This is ethics of virtues and moral character, for moral virtues form the truly good character of the agent with respect to the goal of a truly good and happy life. In general, the various forms of virtue ethics are classified as the ethics of benevolence and charity and the ethics of prosocial care. In this paper we consider some of the basic elements of virtue ethics in confrontation with selected ideas of representatives of trans- and post-humanism. The most important element is the idea of the morally good subject, from which all the others derive. This idea implies the requirement to specify at least some ethical principles, the application of which will ensure that one acts truly well and right when using techno-technological artefacts.

2 Methods

The study uses the method of critical analysis of the views of selected representatives of trans- and post-humanism and some of their critics regarding the basic elements of virtue ethics. The study will focus particularly on the analysis of the idea of the moral subject, virtue and happiness and will offer initial options with respect to an integral and comprehensive vision of virtue ethics.

2.1 Trans- and Post-humanism

Today, transhumanism is developing as a complex technical-scientific, philosophical, socio-economic, political and cultural trend. According to Róbert Sarka: “It is a philosophical futuristic vision that deals, among other things, with the idea of transforming the human body using modern technology. The goal is the integration of the artificial and the organic. The vision is of a robotic human, a homobot. According to the adherents of transhumanism, with the help of advanced technologies it will be possible to eliminate aging and expand the intelligence, physical and psychological capabilities of man.” (Sarka, 2009, p. 190). Transhumanism is supposed to represent a transitional period to the so-called posthuman age. Representatives of posthumanism as a complex futuristic philosophical-scientific-technical direction assume that one day there will be beings on earth whose basic abilities will so radically exceed those of humans that they cannot be considered, according to established norms, to be uniquely human, which is why they are already assigning them the label of posthuman (Bolter, 2016).

Philosophically, this is a rather materialist and mechanistic understanding of the world that uses a (de)constructivist mode of argumentation, where they do not directly deny metaphysical, spiritual and religious perspectives, but subordinate them to the chosen basic element (functional quality) and to the prevailing functionalist approach, as will be discussed below. At the same time, transhumanists are also open to the living world religions because they see in their doctrines certain overlaps with their ideas and consider them as their predecessors because of their transcending tendency of openness to the immortal, the eternal, the divine within the cultural flourishing of humanity (Levchuk, 2019, pp. 75–77; Ahamed et al., 2019, pp. 701–714).

Patrick D. Hopkins defined four elements of a moral vision for transhumanism: 1. “[…] the first element of a transhumanist moral vision is that the effort to address the human condition requires that we change the physical facts that in part generate the human condition. Curing the human condition requires altering the “human” part of the equation”; 2. “the second element of a reflective transhumanist moral vision is to permit human bodies and brains to catch up with the human mind’s projects, to fulfill the human desire for its own idealized construction and pursuits”; 3. “the third element of a reflective transhumanist moral vision is that our very psyches themselves, our very moral natures, are not finished projects but can be altered as well. As we are, we are not suited to be as good as we can be. Our characters and wills themselves, as age-old religions and philosophies have taught, are to be transformed into something better”; 4. “the fourth element of a reflective transhumanist moral vision is to seek Truth and pursue the Good – using technology as a tool to change ourselves in such ways that we can learn more, see more, experience more, and understand more, including even more radical ways to change ourselves to seek truth and pursue the good” (Hopkins, 2008, pp. 3–7).

From a socio-economic point of view, transhumanism partly resembles socialism as a transitional system on the way to communism. According to Marxist-Leninist ideology, socialism is an establishment in which there is common ownership of the means of production, the working class rules, and everyone receives (“justly”) according to his or her merits. Communists envisage a classless society in which the common ownership of the means of production is maintained and everyone receives equally according to his needs (the so-called earthly paradise of communist utilitarianism). In the so-called post-human era, the “just” leadership of a classless society would be taken over by cybernetically controlled machines (e.g. robots, artificial intelligences, etc.) that could distribute the goods and meet the needs of the members of the communities better, more perfectly, and more impartially than humans have been able to do so far as stated later (Lee, 2019a, pp. 849–863). For these and other reasons, Francis Fukuyma identified transhumanism as the most dangerous idea today, as it threatens the established democratic order in society (Fukuyma, 2004). More recently, Paul Cullen has described transhumanism as an anti-humanism that carries many dangers (Cullen, 2022).

According to Emil Višňovský, transhumanism, which embraces the idea of posthumanism, is superhumanismin the sense of the transcendence and perfection of man beyond his natural or biological limits and possibilities. […] Although transhumanists may agree with humanists […] that man is a being striving for perfection and capable of enhancement, it is the question of the character or nature of man on which they diverge. If, for humanists, man as we know him, i.e. as a natural-cultural being, is the highest value, then they will want to preserve this value. Transhumanists either have a different highest value, i.e. they conceive of man as a different, artificial being, or they have a different concept of human nature; one that can and must be “overcome,” transcended.” (Višňovský, 2019, pp. 176–177) For these reasons, it is necessary to specify and evaluate selected moral elements of trans- and post-humanism.

2.2 Moral Subject

Trans- and post-humanists consider the following to be sentient entities (animate or inanimate): humans (even genetically modified), cybernetic organisms, artificial/digital intelligences, “intellectually” enhanced plants and animals, and other intellectually living creatures (e.g. extraterrestrials). In 2014, American columnist Zoltan Istvan Gyurko founded the U.S. Transhumanist Party, which promotes social recognition of rights for non-living sentient entities (Lee, 2019b, pp. 18–19; Stolyarov II, 2019). In 2017, Saudi Arabia – the first country in the world – conferred citizenship on a robot with the likeness of a woman. Its developer is robot designer Davide Hanson and he named it Sofia. The robot Sofia is also programmed to make emotional expressions (Stone, 2017). A sentient entity should be understood as an entity (thing) that is capable of perception, awareness, and experience of itself and others. The quality of this ability depends on the intelligence assigned to it – sentient intelligence – which is held by the respective entities (Kelley, 2019; Morris, 2018a,b; Thurzo, 2021). For example, the Dutch futurist Amanda Stoel speaks of “degrees of personhood” in the sentient entities. These degrees would be measured on the basis of a scale that takes into account all the capacities and attributes possessed by an entity that together constitute personhood (e.g. self-awareness, self-determination, autonomous decision-making, intentionality, etc.). Consequently, rights would be assigned to these entities according to the degree of personhood that is measured in them (Stoel, 2019, pp. 628–629). The ability to perceive and feel presupposes a functional basis in these entities: either organic (physiological, related to the activity of the nervous system) or also artificial (techno-technological).

This understanding of the (moral) subject is possible because dignity is understood as an accident – a functional, measurable, removable, or changeable (improved or diminished) quality. This meaning of dignity as a quality has been advanced by Oxford philosopher Nick Bostrom (Bostrom, 2008).[1] Similarly, Ingmar Persson and Julian Savulescu also applied the principle of self-awareness to define a person who would not be related to the biological species Homo sapiens (Person & Savulescu, 2010). According to the German thinker Stefan L. Sorgner, man has always been a cybernetic organism (Sorgner, 2022). The Israeli posthumanist Yuval N. Harari considers humans as a surpassed organic algorithm and conceives their life as data processing (Harari, 2019, loc. 80–93, 351, 358, 364, 366).

These transhumanist views echo the Enlightenment empirical definition of the person by John Locke (1632–1704), who understood the person as an entity (thing) that psychologically knows itself. Insofar as it experiences itself, it possesses itself and can freely (autonomously) dispose of itself (Locke, 1690, p. 103; Locke, 2007, pp. 84, 115). At the end of the last century, Australian thinker Peter Singer applied this definition of person to those living animals that are capable of psychological self-awareness and emotional interaction. At the same time, Singer limited the application of the concept of person to those human subjects who do not have these capacities (Singer, 1994, pp. 180–183, 205–206; 1993, pp. 86–87, 190–191, 197). At the beginning of our millennium, Jeff McMahan applied this understanding of the person to justify his ethics of killing human life in its beginning and at its end (McMahan, 2002, pp. 6–7, 444, 67, 80–87, 215, 229, 347–361, 488).

This is the so-called functionalist (not substantivist) interpretation of the person, which represents a radical change in the understanding of the person and promotes deconstructivism. Its representatives seek to effectively deconstruct “old” ideas and replace them with “new” relativistic constructs whose meaning is mutable (fluid) according to the chosen need (Rajský, 2021, pp. 108–109; Rajský, 2007, p. 9). This is truly a revolution – not only theoretical, but also practical (social) (Harari, 2019, loc. 252), the aim of which is the deification of humanity by technical-technological tools. According to Harari, only a person empowered with “divine” abilities can survive (Harari, 2019, loc. 25). This vision echoes the Nietzschean idea of the superman (Nietzsche, 2013, pp. 11, 25–26) and resonates the Darwinian-inspired idea of evolutionary selection (Darwin, 1996) and Spencerʼs idea of the survival of the fittest, i.e. enhanced being (Spencer, 1864).[2]

2.3 Moral Virtues, Bio-happiness and Peace

In the spirit of Enlightenment values, American sociologist James J. Hughes, co-founder and director of the Institute for Ethics and Emerging Technologies at the University of Massachusetts (Boston, USA), developed the concept of democratic transhumanism. This will be followed by a transhumanist democracy, whose members will include cyborgs (Hughes, 2004, pp. 187–240; Hughes, 2002). According to Hughes, we have an ethical obligation to enhance ourselves (genetically, bio-chemically, cybernetically) in order to live longer, better and wiser through the advances of science and democracy (Hughes, 2004, pp. 3–42). Hughes understands virtues as those social competencies that are to ensure a happy life (bio-happiness) in the sense of eudaimonia (i.e. a dynamic focus on the good life as a whole, not just a kind of occasional pleasure) (Hughes, 2004, pp. 43–52). Hughes defines seven human/moral virtues: temperance, perseverance, compassion (Hughes, 2004, pp. 241–257), justice, mindfulness, intelligence and transcendence (Hughes, 2011). These virtues ensure that the use of enhancing technologies is safe, accessible to all, and respects the rights of individuals to self-control (including of their bodies) (Hughes, 2004, pp. 11–22; Hughes, 2011). Hughes further develops these ideas in a Buddhist sense. Under his leadership, The Cyborg Buddha Project (CBP) was established, where participants seek to link neurosciences, technologies, transhumanism and Buddhism on a way to liberate the human ‘self’ from suffering to a so-called ‘posthuman’ state (Evans, 2014; Hughes, 2007; Ross, 2019, pp. 141–161).

Inessa Lee, a member of the California Transhumanist Party (Los Angeles, USA), goes even further. In the line of previous transhumanist manifestos (Esfandiary, 1973; Haraway, 1985; Vita-More, 1983, 1998, 2008, 2020), she eclectically and unjustifiably combines the ideas of Marxism and (deistically understood) Christianity in the conception of a transhumanist egalitarian socio-economic theory that aims at a new paradise on earth in this post-Christian era. This conception is expressed by the following Leeʼs equation: (science + technology + economics) × faith = egalitarianism (Lee, 2019a, p. 859). Lee assumes that new technologies will put an end to social stratification through the equal redistribution of resources in an era of technological singularity. According to her, the current social stratification is the result of unequal distribution of resources on the planet. It is the main cause of human suffering, disorder and wars. In order to eradicate poverty and achieve world peace, material wealth and resources should be distributed equally. New technologies should be used to ensure that the world is run by artificial intelligence, thereby ending socio-economic inequality, diseases and suffering. This new egalitarianism is to represent the highest stage of capitalism’s development within the framework of a progressive transhumanist (non-violent and inevitable) revolution. Lee therefore proclaimed the Equalism Manifesto and Equalismʼs 10 Commandments.

The Equalism Manifesto includes the following seven socio-economic strategies: 1. State-owned means of production, lands and enterprises; abolition of inherited properties, including intellectual ones (cf. Leviticus 25:23; Job 41:11). 2. Elimination of human exploitation by full automation of labor. 3. Active use of Digital Democracy to expand and improve democratic practice. 4. Replacing governments with supercomputers until Godʼs Kingdom is restablished during the Second coming of Christ (cf. Apocalypse 19:16). 5. Establishing centrally planned economy managed by Artificial Intelligence. 6. Eliminating money with the help of advanced technology. 7. Free healthcare and education for all people (Lee, 2019a, pp. 854–857).

In the Equalismʼs 10 Commandments, Lee states the following moral imperatives: 1. Let there be equality between you as you are equal before God (cf. Exodus 16:18, 2 Corinthians 8:14). 2. Love God with all your heart as you are created in His image (cf. Matthew 22:37). 3. Love and accept thyself and your neighbor the way God created you (cf. Mark 12.31). 4. Treat each other as brothers and sisters for you are all Godʼs children (cf. Hebrews 13:1). 5. Honor your family, for without them you are like a rootless tree (cf. Proverbs 11:29). 6. Preserve nature as God created it before breathing life into you (cf. Genesis 1:26). 7. Keep your mind pure, as impure thoughts make your body uncean (cf. 1 Corinthians 5:11). 8. Do not harm your neighborʼs body or soul as they are created by God (cf. Romans 13:9). 9. Forgive each other as God is forgiveness (cf. Colossians 3:13). 10. Seek for true love, not for material possessions (cf. 1 Peter 4:8). According to Lee, this is how people are supposed to build a new world paradise[3] because of true love in the name of the Triune God. It is a Christian-Communist cyberocracy (Lee, 2019a, pp. 860–862).

3 Results

It follows that trans- and post-humanists tend to reduce moral goodness to functional (genetic, bio-chemical, or techno-technological) utility; moral act to functional (genetic, bio-chemical, or techno-technological) practicability; moral virtue to (genetically, bio-chemically or techno-technologically) enhanced social competence; moral law to functionally enhanced (genetically, bio-chemically or techno-technologically) legalism; moral happiness to the result of (genetically, bio-chemically or techno-technologically) enhanced interventions and processes. This compromises traditional moral elements, especially the concept of virtue as the historically oldest ethical element (Strahovnik, 2021). However, (genetic, bio-chemical or techno-technological) enhancement as such alone is incapable of comprehensively ensuring man’s cultural (moral) perfection and peaceful coexistence among human beings, which is why many thinkers propose an orderly cultural and integral enhancement of man that incorporates his moral (human) and spiritual aspects in the dynamics of his life in the world (Benanti, 2018, 2016, loc. 125–144; Farbák & Plašienková, 2021; Plašienková & Farbák, 2022, 2021a, 2021b, 2020).

4 Discussion

In the context of the ongoing global debate regarding trans- and post-humanist ideas, Višňovský reminds us that it is not enough to ask what we are going to make of ourselves, but also to ask: What is man to man? “Because the value of man to man – the value of human beings to each other – is the fundamental that makes us human. If we lose this value (and our sense of it), we lose our humanity and with it our human future. Unless we were no longer aware of it today.” (Višňovský, 2020, 79–80) Therefore he proposes a way homo homini hominus (Višňovský, 2020, p. 10). This is the path of a pro-social approach, which is also followed by many others (e.g. Rajský et al., 2014). An artificial intelligence/robot cannot recognize and perceive the deep humanity in another personʼs face; it can only record signs, information, data, etc. and interpellate them according to selected criteria. Artificial intelligence/robot cannot be truly pro-social and (morally) virtuous; thus it cannot adopt the “specific and unique way of seeing, judging and responding to the needs and dependence of the other” man (Rajský et al., 2018, p. 184).

According to Sarka, the representatives of trans- and post-humanism understand technology solely in order to reinforce anthropocentrism, more precisely ego-theism. There is the deification of the human “I”, a new way of celebrating the enhanced modified body, which is understood as a transitional form (dimension). This ego-theism manifests as self-transformation and self-direction. Self-transformation represents physical, intellectual, and moral growth through specifically understood rationality, creativity, personal responsibility, and experimentation, as we indicated earlier. Self-direction consists of resistance to democratic authority, which is replaced by individual autonomy and/or robot/artificial intelligence, as we have also shown with examples of the ideas of selected representatives of trans- and post-humanism (Sarka, 2017, p. 122; 2009, p. 190).

The American Lutheran theologian Theodore F. Peters recently wrote about the dangers of abusing technological progress in a trans- and post-humanist sense: “I tis my own view that the utopian endgame of secular transhumanism ich based on a false scientific assumption regarding the relationship between evolution and progress, and H+ is naïve when underestimating the human capacity for destructive evil. No amount of technical advance can either liberate human race from its current sinful state or police our propensity for prostituting every technology in the service of injustice.” (Peters, 2022, p. 23).

Contemporary American lawyer and thinker Wesley J. Smith, co-founder and chairman of the Discovery Instituteʼs Center on Human Exceptionalism (Seattle, Washington State, USA), recently described transhumanism as pure eugenics and rejected Harariʼs idea about unimproved humans, writing: “It is tempting to fall prey to such nihilism. But resistance is not futile if we continually remind ourselves that no human life is ever “meaningless” or “worthless”. And even if Harari is right that we will eventually devolve into a Brave New World[4]caste system, the unenhanced still would retain the most important and powerful human characteristic of all: the ability to love. Love isn’t something that transhumanists generally talk much about. I think that’s because it can’t be generated by taking a pill, editing genes, or melding with a computer algorithm. It isn’t transactional. The ability to love comes from being loved and practicing the virtues. No high-tech shortcuts. How boring. This is transhumanism’s fatal flaw. To paraphrase a great saint, “If I blend with an AI computer program and can fathom all mysteries and all knowledge, and if I have enhanced capacities that can move mountains, but do not have love, I am nothing.”” (Smith, 2022).

5 Conclusion

From the presented research is evident that the selected ideas of trans- and post-humanists challenge us to re-justify and defend: 1. the uniqueness of the human being (person) as a moral subject in its complex relational body-mind-spirit unity; 2. the uniqueness of the human act as a moral act; 3. the nature and significance of virtue as a moral disposition for a truly good life; 4. the nature and significance of happiness as a true complex eudaimonia; 5. a holistic understanding of progress in relation to the previous elements of virtue ethics; 6. the significance of technical artefacts and technologies as assistance to humanity. We are aware that the list of these challenges is not closed. There remains an open space for further research on the topic.

For the correct application of these challenges in everyday life, it is necessary to define the relevant ethical principles (so-called algor-ethics/ethical algorithm), the quantitative and qualitative specification of which remains open for further research. Let us mention at least some of them: 1. Techno-technological artefacts serve for the real good of man and society, as they are in principle transparently explainable. 2. These artefacts must work reliably (reliability). 3. They should work securely respecting the privacy of users. 4. Their authors must proceed responsibly and transparently in their creation. 5. Their authors are to act impartially; they must not act in a biased/partial interest way; they are to act in a fair way respecting the dignity of every human being. 6. The creation and use of the techno-technological artefacts must take into account the needs of all people, so that everyone can benefit from them and all individuals are provided the best possible conditions for self-fulfilment and development in their use (Pontifical Academy for Life, Microsoft, IBM, FAO, Ministry of Innovation of Italian Republic, 2020; Benanti, 2018). In this way, a truly peaceful social life in love will be ensured for future generations.


Corresponding author: Michal Vivoda, Department of Systematic Theology, Faculty of Roman Catholic Theology of Cyril and Methodius, Comenius University Bratislava, Kapitulská 26, 81458Bratislava, Slovakia, E-mail:

Funding source: Agentúra na Podporu Výskumu a Vývoja

Award Identifier / Grant number: APVV-18-0103

  1. Research funding: This research was funded by the Slovak Research and Development Agency under contract no. APVV-18-0103: Paradigmatic Changes in the Understanding of Universe and Man from Philosophical, Theological, and Physical Perspectives.

References

Ahamed, S., Madan, P., & Singh, A. K. (2019). Transhumanism in India: Past, present and the future. In N. Lee (Ed.), The Transhumanism Handbook (pp. 701–714). Springer.10.1007/978-3-030-16920-6_56Search in Google Scholar

Benanti, P. (2016). La condizione techno-umana. Domande di senso nellʼera della tecnologia [The techno-human condition. Questions of meaning in the age of technology]. E-book. Edizioni Dehoniane Bologna.Search in Google Scholar

Benanti, P. (2018). Oracoli. Tra algoretica e algocrazia [Oracles. Between algorethics and algocracy]. E-book. Luca Sossella Editore.Search in Google Scholar

Bolter, J. D. (2016). Poshumanism. In Jensen, K. B., Rothenbuhler, E. W., Pooley, J. D., & Craig, R. T. (Eds.), The International Encyclopedia of Communication Theory and Philosophy. https://repository.library.georgetown.edu/bitstream/handle/10822/559351/human_dignity_and_bioethics.pdf?seq uence=1&isAllowed=y; https://nickbostrom.com/ethics/dignity-enhancement.pdfSearch in Google Scholar

Bostrom, N. (2008). Dignity and enhacement. In The Presidentʼs Council on Bioethics. Human Dignity and Bioethics: Essays Commissioned by the President’s Council on Bioethic (pp. 173–207). https://bioethicsarchive.georgetown.edu/pcbe/reports/human_dignity/chapter8.html; https://repository.library.georgetown.edu/bitstream/handle/10822/559351/human_dignity_and_bioethics.pdf?sequence=1&isAllowed=y; https://nickbostrom.com/ethics/dignity-enhancement.pdfSearch in Google Scholar

Cullen, P. (2022). Transhumanism: Optimized dream or disappoimting nightmare? [23 march]. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=B80nNqaKbckSearch in Google Scholar

Darwin, C. (1996). Pôvod druhov [The Origin of species (1859)]. Kalligram.Search in Google Scholar

Esfandiary, F. M. (1973). Up-wingers. A futurist manifesto. John Day Company, E-Reads. https://slowlorisblog.files.wordpress.com/2015/05/esfandiary-up-wingers-a-futurist-manifesto.pdfSearch in Google Scholar

Evans, W. (2014). If you see a cyborg in the road, kill the Buddha: Against transcendental transhumanism. Journal of Evolution and Technology, 24(2), 92–97. https://doi.org/10.55613/jeet.v24i2.26.Search in Google Scholar

Farbák, M., & Plašienková, Z. (2021). Morálne biovylepšovanie: Cesta budúcnosti alebo ohrozenie morálneho statusu človeka? [Moral bioenhancement – the path to the future or threat of moral status of human being?]. In Z. Plašienková (Ed.), Bioetické výzvy a súčasnosť z pohľadu nových poznatkov a trendov [Bioethical challenges at present time: in terms of new knowledge and trends] (pp. 75–85). Centrum vedecko-technických informácií SR.Search in Google Scholar

Fukuyma, F. (2004). Transhumanism. Foreign Policy, 144 (September–October), 42–43.10.2307/4152980Search in Google Scholar

Harari, Y. N. (2019). Homo deus. Stručná história zajtrajška [Homo deus. A brief history of tomorrow]. E-book. AKTUEL.Search in Google Scholar

Haraway, D. (1985). A manifesto for cyborgs: Science, technology, and socialist feminism in the 1980s. Socialist Review 80 (March, April), 65–107.Search in Google Scholar

Hopkins, P. D. (2008). A moral vision for transhumanism. Journal of Evolution and Technology, 19(1), 3–7.Search in Google Scholar

Hughes, J. J. (2002). Democratic transhumanism 2.0.Search in Google Scholar

Hughes, J. J. (2004). Citizen cyborg. Why democratic societies must respond to the redesigned human of the future. Westview Press.Search in Google Scholar

Hughes, J. J. (2007). The compatibility of religious and transhumanist views of metaphysics, suffering, virtue and transcendence in an enhanced future. Global Spiral, 8(1).Search in Google Scholar

Hughes, J. J. (2011). After happiness, cyborg virtue. Free Inquiry, 32(1).Search in Google Scholar

Huxley, A. (1932). Brave new world. https://www.huxley.net/bnw/eighteen.htmlSearch in Google Scholar

Kelley, D-J. (2019). The sapient and sentient intelligence value argument and effects on regulating autonomous artificial intelligence. In N. Lee (Ed.), The Transhumanism Handbook (pp. 175–187). Springer.10.1007/978-3-030-16920-6_7Search in Google Scholar

Kolnai, A. (1976). Dignity. Philosophy, 51(197), 251–271. https://doi.org/10.1017/s003181910001932x.Search in Google Scholar

Lee, I. (2019a). Equalism: Paradise regained. In N. Lee (Ed.), The Transhumanist Handbook (pp. 849–863). Springer.10.1007/978-3-030-16920-6_66Search in Google Scholar

Lee, N. (2019b). Brave new world of transhumanism. In N. Lee (Ed), The Transhumanism Handbook (pp. 3–48). Springer.10.1007/978-3-030-16920-6_1Search in Google Scholar

Levchuk, K. (2019). How transhumanism will get us through the third millennium. In N. Lee (Ed.), The Transhumanism Handbook (pp. 75–88). Springer.10.1007/978-3-030-16920-6_4Search in Google Scholar

Locke, J. (1690). Two treatises of government. https://www.thefederalistpapers.org/wp-content/uploads/2012/12/Two-Treatises-of-Government-by-John-Locke.pdfSearch in Google Scholar

Locke, J. (2007). In J. Bennett (Ed.), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding in Four Books. https://www.earlymoderntexts.com/assets/pdfs/locke1690book2.pdfSearch in Google Scholar

McMahan, J. (2002). The ethics of killing. Problems at the margins of life. Oxford University Press.10.1093/0195079981.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Morris, A. (2018a). Can you be a person if youʼre not human? Forbes (13 march). https://www.forbes.com/sites/andreamorris/2018/03/13/can-you-be-a-person-if-youre-not-human/?sh=3b72357f2f7fSearch in Google Scholar

Morris, A. (2018b). We need to talk about sentient robots. Forbes (13 March). https://www.forbes.com/sites/andreamorris/2018/03/13/we-need-to-talk-about-sentient-robots/?sh=1b5a09461b2cSearch in Google Scholar

Nietzsche, F. (2013). Tak pravil Zarathustra. Kniha pre všechny a pro nikoho [Also Sprach Zarathustra. Ein Buch für Alle und keinen (1883–1885)]. Vyšehrad.10.1524/9783050057385Search in Google Scholar

Person, I., & Savulescu, J. (2010). Moral transhumanism. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy: A Forum for Bioethics and Philosophy of Medicine 35(6), 656–669. https://doi.org/10.1093/jmp/jhq052Search in Google Scholar

Peters, T. F. (2022). Homo deus or Frankensteinʼs monster? Religious transhumanism and its critics. In A. M. Gouw, B. P. Green, & T. F. Peters (Eds.), Religious Transhumanism and Its Critics (pp. 3–30). The Rowman & Littlefiled Publishing Group.Search in Google Scholar

Plašienková, Z., & Farbák, M. (2020). Chemical dehumanisation of love vs authentic evolution of love. Philosophy and Public Issues, 10(3), 227–252.Search in Google Scholar

Plašienková, Z., & Farbák, M. (2021a). Happiness issue – moral aspects of its biochemical enhancement. Studia Ecologiae et Bioethicae, 19(3), 17–24. https://doi.org/10.21697/seb.2021.19.3.02.Search in Google Scholar

Plašienková, Z., & Farbák, M. (2021b). Healthy people and biochemical enhancement: A new paradigmatic approach to the enhancement of human beings. Ethics & Bioethics, 11(3–4), 231–239.https://doi.org/10.2478/ebce-2021-0020Search in Google Scholar

Plašienková, Z., & Farbák, M. (2022). Paradigmatické zmeny v chápaní podstaty ľudskosti – transhumanizmus a mentálne postihnutí [Paradigmatic changes in the understanding of the humanity – transhumanism and mentally disabled people]. RaN (Radosť a nádej). Spoločensko-duchovná revue [(Joy and Hope). Social-spiritual review], 24(1), 16–26.Search in Google Scholar

Pontifical Academy for Life, Microsoft, IBM, FAO, Ministry of Innovation of Italian republic. (2020). The Rome Call for AI Ethics (28 February 2020). https://www.romecall.org/wp-content/uploads/2022/03/RomeCall_Paper_web.pdfSearch in Google Scholar

Rajský, A. (2007). Osoba ako ikona tajomstva. Príspevok k personalistickej filozofii [The person as an icon of mystery. A contribution to personalist philosophy]. Trnavská univerzita v Trnave.Search in Google Scholar

Rajský, A. (2021). Filozofia výchovy. Vybrané state [Philosophy of education. Selected parts]. Trnavská univerzita v Trnave.Search in Google Scholar

Rajský, A., Podmanický, I., Brestovanský, M., Zeleiová Gajdošíková, J., Dojčár, M., Kaliský, J., Kusý, P., Mari, G., Milan, G., Sádovská, A., Smékal, V., Szeliga, P., Šuleková, M., & Wiesenganger, M. (2014). Prosociálnosť a etická výchova. Skúsenosti a perspektívy [Prosociality and ethical education. Experiences and perspectives]. Trnavská univerzita v Trnave.Search in Google Scholar

Rajský, A., Wiesenganger, M., Nemec, R., Ondrej, P., Rusnák, P., Šarníková, G., & Šuleková, M. (2018). Pomoc druhému na ceste cnosti. K filozoficko-etickým aspektom prosociálnosti [Helping another on the path of virtue. On the philosophical and ethical aspects of prosociality]. Trnavská univerzita v Trnave.Search in Google Scholar

Ross, B. J. (2019). Transhumanism: On Ontology of the Worldʼs Most Dangerous Idea [Dissertation Prepared for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy]. University of North Texas. https://digital.library.unt.edu/ark:/67531/metadc1505282/m2/1/high_res_d/ROSS-DISSERTATION-2019.pdfSearch in Google Scholar

Sarka, R. (2009). Svedomie, roboetika, transhumanizmus. Teologické texty, 20(4/125*), 188–193.Search in Google Scholar

Sarka, R. (2017). Katechéta a súčasná veda [The catechist and contemporary science]. VERBUM – vydavateľstvo Katolíckej univerzity v Ružomberku.Search in Google Scholar

Singer, P. (1993). Practical ethics. Cambridge University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Singer, P. (1994). Rethinking life and death. The collapse of our traditional ethics. St: Martinʼs Press.Search in Google Scholar

Smith, W. J. (2022). Transhumanism is pure eugenics. Evolution News & Science Today (27 April). https://evolutionnews.org/2022/04/transhumanism-is-pure-eugenics/Search in Google Scholar

Sorgner, S. L. (2022). We have always been cyborgs. Digital data, gene, technologies, and ethics of transhumanism. Bristol University Press.10.1332/policypress/9781529219203.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Spencer, H. (1864). The Principles of biology (Vol. I). Williams and Norgate. https://archive.org/details/principlesbiolo05spengoog/page/n2/mode/2upSearch in Google Scholar

Stoel, A. (2019). The meme of altruism and degrees of personhood. In N. Lee (Ed.), The Transhumanism Handbook (pp. 623–631). Springer.10.1007/978-3-030-16920-6_44Search in Google Scholar

Stolyarov, G.II (2019). The United States transhumanist party and the politics of abundance. In N. Lee (Ed.), The Transhumanism Handbook (pp. 89–149). Springer.10.1007/978-3-030-16920-6_5Search in Google Scholar

Stone, Z. (2017). Everything you need to know about Sophia. The Worldʼs First Robot Citizen. Forbes (7 November). https://www.forbes.com/sites/zarastone/2017/11/07/everything-you-need-to-know-about-sophia-the-worlds-first-robot-citizen/?sh=497dce6d46faSearch in Google Scholar

Strahovnik, V. (2021). Virtues and transhumanist human enhancement. In R. Petkovšek, & B. Žalec (Eds.), Transhumanism as a Challange for Ethics and Religion (pp. 37–44). LIT Verlag.Search in Google Scholar

Thurzo, V. (2021). The influence of existencialism and subjectivism on the concept of human person. In Maturkanič, P., Bělík, V., Dolista, J., Hanušová, J., Hlad, Ľ., Judák, V., Kučírek, J., Lepeška, J., Lorencová, R., Medzihorský, Š., Morávková, S., Rychnová, S., Sedláček, J., Hoferková Svoboda, S., Šimonová, V., Šulík, I., Tomanová Čergeťová, I., & Zimny, J. (Eds.), Spiritual and Social Experience in the Context of Modernism and Postmodernism. Interdisciplinary Reading of the Phenomen (pp. 7–34). Lulu Publishing Company.Search in Google Scholar

Višňovský, E. (2019). Veda ako sociokultúrna praktika [Science as sociocultural practice]. Univerzita Komenského v Bratislave.10.46854/fc.2020.4r.499Search in Google Scholar

Višňovský, E. (2020). Spytovanie na človeka [Inquiry on man]. Univerzita komenského v bratislave. https://fphil.uniba.sk/fileadmin/fif/katedry_pracoviska/kfdf/Personal/Visnovsky/Publikacie/Visnovsky-SPYTOVANIE_SA_NA_CLOVEKA.pdfSearch in Google Scholar

Vita-More, N. (2020). Transhumanist manifesto (1983, 1998, 2008). https://natashavita-more.com/transhumanist-manifesto/Search in Google Scholar

Received: 2022-11-22
Revised: 2023-01-28
Accepted: 2023-02-01
Published Online: 2023-03-14
Published in Print: 2023-06-27

© 2023 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston

Downloaded on 20.5.2024 from https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/humaff-2022-1004/html
Scroll to top button