Skip to main content
Log in

Two Versions of Meaning Failure: A Contributing Essay to the Explanation of the Split Between Analytical and Phenomenological Continental philosophy

  • Published:
Husserl Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Theories of meaning developed within the analytic tradition, starting with Gottlob Frege, and within continental philosophy, starting with Husserl, can be distinguished by their disagreement about the phenomenon of collapse or failure of meaning. Our text focuses on Frege’s legacy, taken up by Rudolph Carnap, which culminated in a view of the collapse of meaning defined first by a purely syntactic conception of categorial error and second, when Tarski entered the scene, by the paradoxes created by the conflict between the use of the predicate truth and the concept of proof. As positivism’s conventionalism and late model-theoretic semantics became the paradigms derived from this position, the result, in our view, was a conception of meaning success and meaning failure dominated by dependence on a technological conception. We will argue that this dependence leads to the inability to evaluate the breaks in rational parameters and crises of meaning addressed by the phenomenological and transcendental perspectives. Husserl’s critique of logic as technology is the basis for the reflexive standpoint on the phenomena of meaning failure that leads to a theoretical and eidetic ideal approach to that phenomenon. It is then suggested that this phenomenological reflective standpoint on the problem of meaning failure is the origin of the doors that lead to the divergent paths between the analytic and continental traditions. Thus, this is an article with three argumentative phases connected into a larger unity. The first phase presents Husserl’s critique of a purely extensional, syntactic, and recursive conception of logical consequence and the concept of truth; the second presents Hussel’s larger conception of meaning-failure; the third—presented in an appendix— presents a lesson on the division between continental and analytic philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. According to van Heijenoort (1967), there are two fundamental lines of thought in the history of modern logic: logic as a language represented paradigmatically by Frege’s conceptual notation and logic as a calculus represented mainly by logic algebra.

  2. Dummett (1991) takes a semantic stance on the meaning of logical constants.

  3. What he called “logic as philosophy of science” (1969, 102).

References

  • Carnap, R. (1935). Philosophy and logical syntax. Journal of Philosophy, 32(13), 357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1937). The logical syntax of Language. Routledge & Kegan Paul.

  • Carnap, R. (1939). Foundations of logic and mathematics. University of Chicago Press.

  • Carnap, R. (1950). Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4(11), 20–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1963). Intellectual autobiography. In P. A. Schlipp (Ed.), The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. Open Court.

  • Carus, A. W. (2004). : Sellars, Carnap, and the logical space of reasons. In: Awodey S., Klein C. (Eds.), Carnap brought home: The view from Jena (pp. 317-355). Open Court.

  • Dias, D. H. B. (2015). Carnap’s Principle of Tolerance and logical pluralism. Argumentos Revista de Filosofia, 13, 225–236.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1991). The logical basis of metaphysics. Harvard University Press.

  • Etchemendy, J. (1999). The concept of logical consequence. Harvard University Press.

  • Føllesdal, D. (1958). Husserl und Frege: Ein Beitrag zur Beleuchtung der Entstehung der phänomenologischen Philosophie. H. Aschehoug und Co.

  • Frege, G. (1948). Sense and reference. The Philosophical Review, 57(3), 209–230.

  • Glendinning, S. (2006). The idea of continental philosophy. Edinburgh University Press.

  • Greimann, D. (2007). Did Frege really consider truth as an object? Grazer Philosophische Studien, 75(1), 125–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horsten, L. (2011). The Tarskian turn: Deflationism and axiomatic truth. MIT Press.

  • Horwich, P., & Wright, C. (1996). Realism minus truth: truth and objectivity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 56(4), 877.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1969). Formal and transcendental logic. Translated by Dorion Cairns. Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

  • Husserl, E. (1983). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy. Translated by F. Kersten. Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

  • Husserl, E. (2001). Logical investigations. Translated by J.N. Findlay. Routledge.

  • Kripke, S. (1975). Outline of a theory of truth. Journal of Philosophy, 72(19), 690–716.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lavers, G. (2016). Frege the Carnapian and Carnap the Fregean. In S. Costreie (Ed)., Early analytic philosophy – new perspectives on the tradition (pp. 353–373). New York: Springer.

  • Mohanty, J. N. (1982). Husserl and Frege. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Ruin, H. (2011). Seeing meaning: Frege and Derrida on ideality and the limits of Husserlian intuitionism. Husserl Studies, 27(1), 63–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (2009). Collected essays. 1929–1968 (2 vol.). Routledge.

  • Schurz, G. (1999). Tarski and Carnap on logical truth--or: what is genuine logic? Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook, 6, 77–94.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. (1969). Truth and proof. Scientific American, 220(6), 63–77.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Torfehnezhad, P. (2016). In Carnap’s defense: A survey on the concept of a linguistic framework in Carnap’s philosophy. Abstracta, 9(1), 3–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vallor, S. (2005). “The intentionality of reference in husserl and the analytic tradition.” In G. Forrai & Kampis, G (Eds.), Intentionality: Past and Future (pp. 111–125). New York: Rodopi.

  • Van Heijenoort, J. (1967). Logic as calculus and logic as language. Synthese, 17(3), 324–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.

  • Zahavi, D. (2003). Husserl’s phenomenology. Stanford University Press.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the reviewers and referees of the journal who helped shape this article by providing valuable suggestions and corrections. I would also like to thank my friend and author Gregory E. Desilet for proofreading the manuscript and for earlier conversations and discussions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lucas Ribeiro Vollet.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Vollet, L.R. Two Versions of Meaning Failure: A Contributing Essay to the Explanation of the Split Between Analytical and Phenomenological Continental philosophy. Husserl Stud 40, 1–23 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-023-09336-6

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-023-09336-6

Keywords

Navigation