Skip to main content

Mechanism, Emergence, and Miscibility: The Autonomy of Evo-Devo

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Functions: selection and mechanisms

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 363))

Abstract

Evolutionary developmental biology shows us that the capacities of organisms play an indispensable role in the explanation of adaptive evolution. In particular, the goal-directed properties of organisms figure in a class of emergent teleological explanations. The role of emergent teleology has heretofore gone ­unnoticed largely because of modern biology’s methodological commitment to mechanism. I outline and defend an alternative to mechanism: explanatory emergence. According to explanatory emergence, every phenomenon has a complete mechanistic explanation, yet some phenomena also have emergent teleological explanations. Mechanistic and emergent teleological explanations of the same ­phenomena are complete, complementary and autonomous. I call this relation ‘­miscibility’. I argue that the miscibility of explanations illuminates the distinctive character of recent evolutionary developmental biology (evo-devo). Evo-devo offers a class of emergent explanations that advert to the unique capacities of organisms.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    I take the expression ‘thick’ causal concepts from Cartwright (2004).

  2. 2.

    The description dependence of explanations is well documented. Davidson (1967), for example, draws our attention to the fact that while causal contexts sustain the intersubstitution of co-referring descriptions salva veritate, explanatory contexts do not. The reason is that the explanatory content of an explanation is sensitive to the way the relation between explanans and explanandum is described.

  3. 3.

    I leave open the possibility that xc,1 = xc,2. It is, in fact, commonplace that one and the same relation should be susceptible to different explanatory descriptions.

  4. 4.

    Illingworth (2008) offers a nice overview of muscle function.

  5. 5.

    See, for example, Machamer et al. (2000) claim that explanatory properties occur in nested hierarchies. Craver’s (2007) mechanistic anti-fundamentalism and Jackson and Pettit’s (2004) ‘explanatory ecumenism’ are also good examples of an implicit commitment to description relativity.

  6. 6.

    Rosenberg’s (2006) spirited and compelling argument is, in many ways, the definitive defence of reductive mechanism in evolutionary biology.

  7. 7.

    In this I agree with Symons (2008) and Bedau (2008).

  8. 8.

    O’Connor (2000) and Humphreys (1997) attempt to circumvent this problem by arguing that emergent causal properties do not supervene.

  9. 9.

    In the causal modelling literature, ‘intervention’ has a specific technical meaning. One can intervene on xc with respect to xc only if there is a direct causal path from xc to xe (Woodward 2003: 79). I intend to use ‘invariance’ in a less technical sense. There is a change-involving invariance relation between xc and xe just if manipulations on xc are counterfactually related in the right way to the values of xe.

  10. 10.

    Cf. Jackson and Pettit: ‘Explanations of different causal grain are complementary’ (2004: 178).

  11. 11.

    I take it that explanatory autonomy is non-symmetrical. Typically, in a mechanistic reduction the reducing explanation replaces the reduced explanation without explanatory loss but the converse relation does not hold.

  12. 12.

    This distinction between mechanistic and purposive explanations is reminiscent of Bedau’s (1998) distinction between grade 2 and grade 3 teleology. Only in grade 3 (genuine) teleology does the fact that the goal state is a goal appears in the scope of the explanans. Unlike Bedau, however, I do not think that the concept of a goal is inherently normative (2008).

  13. 13.

    I leave open the question whether there are other forms of emergent explanations, although I’m inclined to believe that the argument can be extended to show that there are emergent statistical explanations too.

  14. 14.

    P.W. Anderson’s (1972) famous appeal for emergence is made on the grounds of what I am calling ‘reflexive downward regulation’.

  15. 15.

    It is interesting in this regard that Monod takes his title Chance and Necessity (and his inspiration) from the atomist, Democritus.

  16. 16.

    The original source for the quotation is Eckstein (1980).

References

  • Alexander, S. 1920. Space, time and deity. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen, G.E. 2005. Mechanism, vitalism and organicism in late nineteenth and twentieth-century biology: The importance of historical context. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biology and the Biomedical Sciences 36: 261–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, P.W. 1972. More is different. Science 177: 393–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 2007. Physics Trans. R.P Hardie and R.K. Gray. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/physics.2.ii.html

  • Ayala, F. 1970. Teleological explanations in evolutionary biology. Philosophy of Science 37: 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. 2007. Biological mechanism: Organized to maintain autonomy. In Systems biology, ed. F.C. Boogerd, F.J. Bruggeman, J.-H.S. Hofmeyer, and H.V. Westerhoff, 269–302. Amsterdam: Elsevier B.V.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., and A. Abrahamsen. 2005. Explanation: A mechanist alternative. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biology and Biomedical Sciences 36: 421–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., and R. Richardson. 1993. Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. 1997. Weak emergence. In Philosophical perspectives 11: Mind, causation, and world, ed. J. Tomberlin, 375–399. London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. 1998. Where’s the good in teleology? Repr. In Nature’s purposes: Analyses of function and design in biology, ed. C. Allen, M. Bekoff, and G. Lauder, 261–291. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. 2008. Is weak emergence just in the mind? Minds and Machines 18: 443–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broad, C.D. 1925. Mind and its world. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut, W., G.B. Muller, and S.A. Newman. 2007. The organismic systems approach: Evo Devo and the streamlining of the naturalistic agenda. In Integrating evolution and development: From theory to practice, ed. R. Sansom and B. Brandon, 25–92. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. 2004. Causation: One word, many things. Philosophy of Science 71: 805–819.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. 2007. Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. 1967. Causal relations. Journal of Philosophy 64: 691–703.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. 1982. The selfish gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. 1998. Universal Darwinism. In The philosophy of biology, ed. M. Ruse and D.L. Hull, 15–37. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eckstein, H. 1980. Theoretical approaches to explaining violence. In Handbook of political conflict, ed. T.R. Gurr, 135–167. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S.F., and S. Sarkar. 2000. Embracing complexity: Organicism for the 21st century. Developmental Dynamics 219: 1–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. 1996. Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis 44: 49–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. 2002. Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science 64: 605–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, B. 1994. How the leopard changed its spots: The evolution of complexity. London: Touchstone Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hankinson, J. 2003. Cause and explanation in ancient Greek thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. 1997. How properties emerge. Philosophy of Science 64: S337–S345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P., and P. Humphreys. 2008. Dynamical emergence and computation: An introduction. Minds and Machines 18: 425–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Illingworth, J.A. 2008. Muscle structure and function. www.bmb.leeds.ac.uk/illingworth/muscle/index.htm

  • Jackson, F., and P. Pettit. 2004. In defence of explanatory ecumenism. Repr. In Mind, morality and explanation, ed. F. Jackson, P. Pettit, and M. Smith, 163–185. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M.R. 2005. Aristotle on teleology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. 1970. Articulation of parts explanation in biology and the rational search for them. In Boston studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 8, eds. R.C. Buck and R.S Cohen, 257–272. Boston: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S.A. 1993. The origins of order. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S.A. 1995. At home in the universe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. 1989. Mechanism, purpose and explanatory exclusion. In Philosophical perspectives 3: Philosophy of mind and action theory, ed. J. Tomberlin, 77–108. Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. 2006. Emergence: Core ideas and issues. Synthese 151: 547–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirschner, M., and J. Gerhart. 2005. The plausibility of life: Resolving Darwin’s dilemma. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitano, H. 2004. Biological robustness. Nature Reviews Genetics 5: 826–837.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, F.A. 1988. Teleology and material/efficient causes in Aristotle. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 69: 54–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., L. Darden, and C. Craver. 2000. Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science 57: 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. 1843. A system of logic. London: Longmans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monod, J. 1971. Chance and Necessity. Trans. A. Wainhouse London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muller, G.B. 2007. Evo-devo: Extending the evolutionary synthesis. Nature Reviews Genetics 8: 943–949.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muller, G.B. 2008. Evo-devo as a discipline. In Evolving pathways: Key themes in evolutionary developmental biology, ed. A. Minelli and G. Fusco, 3–29. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. 1977. Teleology revisited. Journal of Philosophy 76: 261–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, S.A., and G.B. Muller. 2007. Genes and form. In Genes in development: Re-reading the molecular paradigm, ed. E. Neuman-Held and C. Rehman-Suter. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman, S.A., G. Forgacs, and G.B. Muller. 2006. Before programs: The physical origination of multi-cellular forms. International Journal of Developmental Biology 50: 289–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, T. 1994. Emergent properties. American Philosophical Quarterly 31: 91–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, T. 2000. Causality, mind and free will. Philosophical Perspectives 14: 105–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S. 1985. The ontogeny of information. Raleigh.: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, R., and A. Stephan. 2007. Mechanism and mechanical explanation in systems biology. In Systems biology, ed. F.C. Boogerd, F.J. Bruggeman, J.-H.S. Hofmeyer, and H.V. Westerhoff, 123–144. Amsterdam: Elsevier B.V.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. 2006. Darwinian reductionism: Or how to stop worrying and love molecular biology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rueger, A. 2000. Robust supervenience and emergence. Philosophy of Science 67: 466–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salazar-Ciudad, I.S., S.A. Newman, and R.V. Sole. 2001. Phenotypic and dynamical transitions in model genetic networks. I. Emergence of patterns and genotype-phenotype relations. Evolution and Development 3: 84–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. 1984. Explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmalhausen, I.I. 1949. Factors of evolution. London: University of Chicago Press (1986).

    Google Scholar 

  • Silbersteen, M., and J. McGeever. 1999. The search for ontological emergence. The Philosophical Quarterly 49: 182–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. 1999. The multiple realizability argument against reductionism. Philosophy of Science 66: 542–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. 2004. The causal and unification approaches to explanation unified—Causally. Nous 38: 154–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Symons, J. 2008. Computational models of emergent properties. Minds and Machines 18: 475–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • True, J.R., and S.B. Carroll. 2002. Gene co-option in physiological and morphological evolution. Annual Reviews of Cell and Developmental Biology 18: 53–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Bertalanffy, L. 1969. General systems theory. New York: George Barziller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Dassow, G., and E. Munro. 1999. Modularity in animal development and evolution: Elements of a conceptual framework for Evo-Devo. Journal of Experimental Zoology (Mole Dev Evol) 285: 307–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D.M. 2007. Teleology. In Oxford handbook of philosophy of biology, ed. M. Ruse, 113–137. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C.K. 1996. Why the antireductionist consensus won’t survive the case of classical Mendelian genetics. Repr. In Conceptual issues in evolutionary biology. 2nd ed., ed. E. Sober, 401–418. Cambridge: MIT, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C.K. 2008. Beyond theoretical reduction and layer-lake anti-reductionism: How DNA retooled genetics and transformed biological practice. In Oxford handbook of philosophy of biology, ed. M. Ruse, 238–262. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Webster, G., and B. Goodwin. 1996. Form and transformation: Generative and relational principles in biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M.J. 2003. Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M.J. 2005a. Phenotypic accommodation: Adaptive innovation due to developmental plasticity. Journal of Experimental Zoology (Mole Dev Evo) 304B: 610–618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M.J. 2005b. Developmental plasticity and the origin of species differences. PNAS 102: 6543–6549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. 2000. Emergence as non-aggregativity and the biases of reductionism. Foundations of Science 5: 269–297. Repr. In Re-engineering philosophy of limited beings, ed. W. Wimsatt, 274–312, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. 2002. What is a mechanism: A counterfactual account. Philosophy of Science 69: S366–S377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. 2003. Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wray, G.A. 2007. The evolutionary significance of cis-regulatory mutations. Nature Reviews Genetics 8: 206–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank audiences in Calgary, Edmonton, Vienna and Paris. In particular, I wish to thank Marc Ereshefsky, Fermin Fulda, Jesse Hendrikse, Philippe Huneman Gerd Muller, and Jacob Stegenga for helpful discussion. The bulk of this chapter was written while I was a visiting fellow at the Konrad Lorenz Institute. I thank all at the KLI for their marvellous hospitality.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Walsh, D.M. (2013). Mechanism, Emergence, and Miscibility: The Autonomy of Evo-Devo. In: Huneman, P. (eds) Functions: selection and mechanisms. Synthese Library, vol 363. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5304-4_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics