Skip to main content
Log in

Character, Common-Sense, and Expertise

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Gilbert Harman has argued that the common-sense characterological psychology employed in virtue ethics is rooted not in unbiased observation of close acquaintances, but rather in the ‘fundamental attribution error’. If this is right, then philosophers cannot rely on their intuitions for insight into characterological psychology, and it might even be that there is no such thing as character. This supports the idea, urged by John Doris and Stephen Stich, that we should rely exclusively on experimental psychology for our explanations of behaviour. The purported ‘fundamental attribution error’ cannot play the explanatory role required of it, however, and anyway there is no experimental evidence that we make such an error. It is true that trait-attribution often goes wrong, but this is best explained by a set of difficulties that beset the explanation of other people’s behaviour, difficulties that become less acute the better we know the agent. This explanation allows that we can gain genuine insight into character on the basis of our intuitions, though claims about the actual distribution of particular traits and the correlations between them must be based on more objective data.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Milgram (1974) himself describes his results in terms of a disposition towards obedience (pp. 1–2 and 42–43). Some thinkers find it implausible to postulate a widespread tendency towards obedience, since people clearly disobey rules all the time in our society. Perhaps we can explain this by saying that people disobey when they think they will not be detected, a condition that does not hold in Milgram’s experiment. But even if this response is unacceptable, we could still agree with Sabini and Silver (2005, pp. 550–551) that the subjects’ behaviour is to be explained in terms of the character trait of deference to expertise.

References

  • Athanassoulis N (2000) Response to Harman: virtue ethics and character traits. Proc Aristot Soc 100(2):215–221

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arkin RM, Duval S (1975) Focus of attention and causal attributions of actors and observers. J Exp Soc Psychol 11:427–438

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris J (1998) Persons, situations, and virtue ethics. Noûs 32(4):504–530

    Google Scholar 

  • Doris J (2002) Lack of character: personality and moral behaviour. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Doris J, Stich S (2005) As a matter of fact: empirical perspectives on ethics. In: Jackson F, Smith M (eds) The Oxford handbook of contemporary philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert DT, Malone PS (1995) The correspondence bias. Psychol Bull 117(1):21–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldie P (2000) The emotions: a philosophical exploration. Clarendon, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldie P (2004) On personality. Routledge, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman G (1999) Moral philosophy meets social psychology: virtue ethics and the fundamental attribution error. Proc Aristot Soc 99(3):315–331

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman G (2000) The nonexistence of character traits. Proc Aristot Soc 100(2):223–225

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones EE, Harris VA (1967) The attribution of attitudes. J Exp Soc Psychol 3(1):1–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamtekar R (2004) Situationism and virtue ethics on the content of our character. Ethics 114(3):458–491

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kupperman J (1991) Character. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • McArthur LZ, Post DL (1977) Figural emphasis and person perception. J Exp Soc Psychol 13(6):520–535

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milgram S (1974) Obedience to authority: an experimental view. Harper and Row, New York

  • Nussbaum MC (1999) Virtue ethics: a misleading category? J Ethics 3(3):163–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross L (1977) The intuitive psychologist and his shortcomings: distortions in the attribution process. In: Berkowitz L (ed), Advances in experimental social psychology, vol. 10. Academic, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross L, Nisbett R (1991) The person and the situation: perspectives of social psychology. McGraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sabini J, Silver M (2005) Lack of character? Situationism critiqued. Ethics 115(3):535–562

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor SE, Fiske ST (1975) Point-of-view and perceptions of causality. J Pers Soc Psychol 32(3):439–445

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trianosky GV (1997) What is virtue ethics all about? In: Statman D (ed) Virtue ethics: a critical reader. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Webber J (2006) Virtue, character and situation. J Moral Philos 3(2):195–216

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper has benefited greatly from discussion at the University of Trieste. I am grateful to Marina Sbisà for organising that event. I am also grateful for very helpful comments from two anonymous referees for this journal.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jonathan Webber.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Webber, J. Character, Common-Sense, and Expertise. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 10, 89–104 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-006-9041-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-006-9041-7

Key words

Navigation