Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Biotechnology as End Game: Ontological and Ethical Collapse in the “Biotech Century”

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
NanoEthics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I argue in this paper that animal biotechnology constitutes a dangerous ontological collapse between animals and the technical-economic apparatus. By ontological collapse, I mean the elimination of fundamental ontological tensions between embodied subjects and the principles of scientific, technological, and economic rationalization. Biotechnology imposes this collapse in various ways: by genetically “reprogramming” animals to serve as uniform commodities, by abstracting them into data and code, and, in some cases, by literally manipulating their movements with computer technologies. These and other forms of ontological violence not only lead to profound physical suffering for the animals involved, but also distort the phenomenological basis of their existence, especially their perceptual experience and expression of subjective time and space. In subordinating nonhuman animals to the logic of “technological rationality” or “technique,” to borrow Herbert Marcuse and Jacques Ellul’s respective terms, biotechnology perpetuates the productive extermination of animals. Biotech animals are exterminated in the sense of being “drive[n] beyond the boundaries” of meaningful existence and “destroyed completely” or “completely wiped out” as subjects. But they are also exterminated in the sense of being “overproduced” and “overgenerated,” both quantitatively and qualitatively. I go on to argue that the collapse of the ontological is accompanied by a collapse of the ethical. This ethical collapse is characterized by the internalization of the logic of technique and the corresponding failure both within technoscientific culture itself and within some scholarly discourses about biotechnology to evaluate from a genuinely critical vantage point the fundamental ethical issues that animal biotechnology raises. The aim of this paper is to offer an alternative analysis of the ontological and ethical implications of biotechnology from the standpoint of Marcuse and Ellul’s critical theory of technology. To explore other ramifications of animal biotechnology, I draw on Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer’s insights into ideologies of extermination and Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology of embodiment.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Hai et al [4]; Best [5]. I also refer to these biotechnologies in the context of a critique of posthumanism in Zipporah Weisberg, “The Trouble with Posthumanism: Bacteria are People Too,” in Critical Animal Studies: Thinking the Unthinkable, ed. John Sorenson (Toronto: Canadian Scholars Press, 2014), 99. I explore a number of the key issues addressed in this article (viz., technological rationality, the symbolic and material integration of animals with the technical apparatus within and beyond the context of biotech, posthumanists’ tendency to glorify technoscience at the expense of ethics, and the derogation of species integrity) in two previous publications: Zipporah Weisberg, “The Trouble with Posthumanism: Bacteria are People Too,” in Critical Animal Studies: Thinking the Unthinkable, ed. John Sorenson (Toronto: Canadian Scholars Press, 2014), 99 and Zipporah Weisberg, The broken promises of monsters: Haraway, animals, and the humanist legacy, Journal for Critical Animal Studies 2:2 (2009). This article develops these ideas into a much more focused and systematic critique of biotechnology as a form of productive extermination than I have hitherto undertaken. I also pay much closer attention here to the phenomenological implications for other animals of genetic manipulation.

  2. Carol Gigliotti, “Introduction,” in Leonardo’s Choice, xii.

  3. I do not wish to reinforce human/animal dualism; however, for the sake of simplicity and clarity, I refer to nonhuman animals (i.e., vertebrates and invertebrates) throughout this paper simply as “animals.”

  4. See, for example, “Expiration Fate: Can ‘De-Extinction’ Bring Back Lost Species?” Scientific American, March 31, 2013, accessed June 11, 2013, http://www.scientificamerican.com/article.cfm?id=what-is-the-de-extinction-movement-all-about.

  5. Webster’s New Twentieth Century Dictionary Unabridged, 2nd ed., s.v. “exterminate.”

  6. Cited in [11]

  7. CCAC guidelines: on procurement of animals used in science [12]. The United Nations Convention on Biological Diversity defines biotechnology as “any technological application that uses biological systems, living organisms, or derivatives thereof, to make or modify products or processes for specific use” (Article 2). UN Convention on Biological Diversity [13] The Canadian Environmental Protection Act (CEPA) describes biotechnology as the “the application of science and engineering in the direct or indirect use of living organisms or parts or products of living organisms in their natural or modified forms.” “What is Biotechnology,” “Canadian Environmental Protection Act, 1999,” Environment Canada, accessed June 5, 2012, http://www.ec.gc.ca/lcpe-cepa/default.asp?lang=En&n=24374285-1&offset=1&toc=show.

  8. “The 1998 Canadian Biotechnology Strategy: An Ongoing Renewal Process,” 1998, Government of Canada: Biostrategy, accessed June 5, 2012, http://www.biostrategy.gc.ca/english/View.asp?pmiid=520&x=535.

  9. Bacon [16]. For a discussion of Bacon’s relevance to modern technoscience, see Weisberg [17].

  10. Rose-Mary Sargent, “Introduction,” in Francis Bacon, xvi.

  11. “Subjects-of-a-life,” on Regan’s definition, are nonhuman animals that “bring the mystery of a unified psychological presence to the world.” Among other things, they “see and hear, believe and desire, remember and anticipate, plan and intend.” I qualify Regan’s definition by emphasizing how meaningful animals’ lives are (to themselves, to each other, and to us) in the phenomenological as well as the conventional sense of the term to which Regan refers. In so doing, I expand the applicability of the category to a much wider array of animals than “mentally normal mammals of a year or more” to which Regan initially restricts it. Tom Regan, The Case for Animal Rights (Berkeley; Los Angeles: University of California Press, 2004), xvi.

  12. See in Weisberg, “The trouble with posthumanism. See especially page 99, where I state, ”These and other transgenic animals are wholly integrated into the machinery of production.”

  13. See note 10, where I indicate that I have discussed this concept of integration elsewhere.

  14. Meidinger et al. [23]; Forsberg et al. [24]; Pollack [25]. In 2010, the Canadian government approved the reproduction of Enviropig, but not its sale and consumption. As a result, Ontario Pork pulled its funding from the project. Another reason the industry backed out was because it turns out that farmers can simply provide their pigs with a supplement to aid digestion of phosphorous at a very low cost, which cancels the need for genetic modifications. When the project was abandoned, the pigs were not rehoused in a sanctuary to live out the rest of their lives in relative peace but were killed and disposed of as biowaste.

  15. Rutherford, Synthetic biology.

  16. Best, “Genetic Science,” 8.

  17. Robo-pigeon, Daily Mail.

  18. Marcuse, One-Dimensional Man, 87; 94.

  19. Horkheimer and Adorno, Dialectic of enlightenment, 9. Rationalization.

  20. Although synthetic biology typically deals with microorganisms and not animals as such, the term is sometimes used interchangeably with biotechnology. See the Fidelity Investment ad cited above, for example.

  21. Rutherford, Synthetic biology.

  22. Gigliotti, Introduction, xvii. Italics added.

  23. Thacker, Data made flesh, 92.

  24. Marcuse, One-dimensional man, 152.

  25. Ian Sample, Craig Venter. Italics added.

  26. Sample, Craig Venter.

  27. Best, Genetic science, 4.

  28. Gigliotti, Introduction, xv–xvi.

  29. Best, Genetic science, 10.

  30. I refer for the first time to the disintegration of transgenic animals in Weisberg, “The trouble with posthumanism,” 99.

  31. Marcuse, One-dimensional man, 125.

  32. Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of perception, 483; 490

  33. Cited in Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of perception, 30.

  34. Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of perception, 292.

  35. Harvey, The condition of postmodernity, 205.

  36. I am borrowing this term from Rifkin, The biotech century, 101

  37. Harvey, The condition of postmodernity, 240.

  38. Marcuse, One-dimensional man, 12.

  39. Newell-McLaughlin and Re, The evolution of biotechnology, 47.

  40. Newell-McLaughlin and Re, The evolution of biotechnology, 48.

  41. Davis, Procrustean solutions, 35.

  42. Cited in Hannah Rubenstein, Goats.

  43. Ellul, The technological society, 74.

  44. Ellul, The technological society, 97.

  45. Ellul, The technological society, 134.

  46. Ellul, The technological society, 134.

  47. Ellul, The technological society, 74.

  48. Ellul, The technological society, 97.

  49. “Annex C: Federal Regulatory Framework for Biotechnology,” The 1998 Canadian Biotechnology Strategy: An Ongoing Renewal Process, 1998, accessed June 5, 2012, http://www.biostrategy.gc.ca/english/View.asp?pmiid=520&x=535.

  50. CCAC guidelines on transgenic animals.

  51. CCAC guidelines on transgenic animals.

  52. This brief critique of some posthumanists’ glorification of hybridity is anticipated by two previously published pieces already cited in this article: Weisberg, “The broken promises of monsters: Haraway, animals, and the humanist legacy”

  53. Twine and Stephens, Introduction, 125.

  54. Weisberg. The trouble with posthumanism. 101–103

  55. Rollin, The ‘Frankenstein thing’, 284.

  56. Rollin, The ‘Frankenstein thing’, 284.

  57. Rollin, The Frankenstein syndrome, 171.

  58. Robert and Baylis, Crossing species boundaries, 6.

  59. Robert and Baylis, Crossing species boundaries, 5.

  60. Robert and Baylis, Crossing species boundaries, 8.

  61. Robert and Baylis, Crossing species boundaries, 7.

  62. Thompson, The opposite of human enhancement, 305–316.

  63. Thompson, The opposite of human enhancement, 308.

  64. Thompson, The opposite of human enhancement, 311.

  65. Thompson, The opposite of human enhancement, 309.

  66. Thompson, The opposite of human enhancement, 309.

  67. Palmer, Animal disenhancement, 45.

  68. Ferrari, Animal disenhancement, 68.

  69. Twine, Is biotechnology deconstructing animal domestication, 146.

  70. Stephens, Growing meat in laboratories, 175.

  71. Stephens, Growing meat in laboratories, 166.

  72. Joy [72] And, as with other non-vegan alternatives such as “humane” farming, IVM would actually encourage people to continue eating factory-farmed meat when IVM was not available. Their conscience would be alleviated because they could reassure themselves that “most of the time,” whenever it is available, they eat cruelty-free IVM instead.

  73. Marcuse, One-dimensional man, 12.

  74. Linzey, Genetic engineering, 325.

  75. Linzey, Genetic engineering, 325.

References

  1. von Feuerbach L (1986) Principles of the philosophy of the future, trans. Manfred Vogel (Indianapolis; Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company), 42

  2. Chan R (2012) Thinking big: synthetic biology. Fidelity Investments. http://thinkingbig.fidelity.com/bio. Accessed June 24, 2012

  3. Anthes E (2013) Don’t be afraid of genetic modification. The New York Times, March 9, 2013. http://www.nytimes.com/2013/03/10/opinion/sunday/dont-be-afraid-of-genetic-modification.html?pagewanted=all&_r=1&. AquaBounty Technologies. 2014. "Products." http://aquabounty.com/company/products/. Accessed March 17, 2013

  4. Hai T et al (2014) One-step generation of knockout pigs by zygote injection of CRISPR/Cas system. Cell Research 24:372–375. doi:10.1038/cr.2014.11. Accessed 29 Oct. 2014

  5. Best S (2011) Genetic science, animal exploitation, and the challenge for democracy. In: Carol G (ed) Leonardo’s choice: genetic technologies and animals. Springer, Dordrecht, p 7

  6. Best S (2013) Genetic science, 9. “GloFish® FAQ,” GloFish®. http://www.glofish.com/about/faq/. Accessed 12 June 2013

  7. Firm hails dog clone breakthrough (2009) BBC News. http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/asia-pacific/7858566.stm. Accessed 11 June 2013

  8. Jørgenson D (2013) Reintroduction and de-extinction. BioScience 63(9):719–720. doi:10.1525/bio.2013.63.9.6

  9. Cohen S (2104) The ethics of de-extinction. NanoEthics 8:165–178. doi:10.1007/s11569-014-0201-2

  10. Derrida J (2008) The animal that therefore I am, trans. In: David W (ed) Marie-Louise Mallet. Fordham University Press, New York, p 26, Italics added

  11. Bud R (1993) The uses of life: a history of biotechnology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, p 1

  12. CCAC guidelines: on procurement of animals used in science (2007) The Canadian Council on Animal Care. http://www.ccac.ca/Documents/Standards/Guidelines/Procurement.pdf. Accessed 17 March 2013

  13. “UN Convention on Biological Diversity (1992)” United Nations. http://www.cbd.int/convention/text/default.shtml. Accessed 22 Feb 2012

  14. Margawati ET (2003) Transgenic animals: their benefits to human welfare. ActionBioscience. http://www.actionbioscience.org/biotech/margawati.html. Accessed 17 March 2013. Italics added

  15. CCAC guidelines: on transgenic animals (1997) The Canadian Council on Animal Care. http://www.ccac.ca/Documents/Standards/Guidelines/Transgenic_Animals.pdf. Accessed 7 May 2013

  16. Bacon F (1999) "New Atlantis,". In: Sargent R-M (ed) Francis Bacon: selected philosophical works. Hackett Publishing Company, Indianapolis, p 263f

  17. Weisberg Z (2009) The broken promises of monsters: Haraway, animals, and the humanist legacy. Journal for Critical Animal Studies 2(2):50

  18. Stix G (2006) The land of milk and money. Scientific American. http://www.scientificamerican.com/article.cfm?id=atryn-the-land-of-milk-and-mone. Accessed 7 May 2013

  19. Rutherford A (2012) Synthetic biology and the rise of ‘spider-goats’. The Guardian. http://www.guardian.co.uk/science/2012/jan/14/synthetic-biology-spider-goat-genetics. Accessed 17 March 2013

  20. Ellul J (1964) The technological society, trans. John Wilkinson. Knopf, New York, p 135

  21. Sample I (2009) Genetically modified monkeys give birth to designer babies. The Guardian. http://www.guardian.co.uk/science/2009/may/27/genetically-modified-gm-monkeys-germline. Accessed 28 May 2012

  22. Cyranoski D (2009) Marmoset model takes centre stage. Nature 459, 492. doi:10.1038/459492a, Accessed 28 Oct. 2014

  23. Meidinger RM et al (2014) The EnviropigTM: reducing the environmental impact of animal agriculture through high health-status pigs that efficiently utilize dietary plant phosphorus. Journal of Biotechnology, IV1-O-001. doi:10.1016/j.jbiotec.2008.07.458, Accessed 28 Oct 2014

  24. Forsberg CW et al (2013) Integration, stability and expression of the E. coli phytase transgene in the Cassie line of Yorkshire Enviropig™. Transgenic Res 22:379–389. doi:10.1007/s11248-012-9646-7, Accessed 28 Oct. 2014

  25. Pollack A (2012) Move to market gene-altered pigs in Canada is halted. The New York Times. http://www.nytimes.com/2012/04/04/science/gene-altered-pig-project-in-canada-is-halted.html. Accessed 27 May 2012. Italics added

  26. Chan R (2013) Thinking big: "Enviropig™". University of Guelph. http://www.uoguelph.ca/enviropig/. Accessed 3 Oct. 2013

  27. Service RF (2002) Mammalian cells spin a spidery new yarn. Science 295. doi:10.1126/science.295.5554.419b, Accessed 28 Oct. 2014

  28. Robo-pigeon: the pigeon that flies wherever you fancy. Daily Mail. http://www.dailymail.co.uk/sciencetech/article-439025/Robo-pigeon-pigeon-flies-fancy.html#ixzz1wHd6SaR6. Accessed 29 May 2012

  29. Carmena JM et al (2003) Learning to control a brain–machine interface for reaching and grasping by primates. PLoS Biology 1: 2 . doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.0000042, Accessed 28 Oc. 2014

  30. Heaven D (2013) First mind-reading implant gives rats telepathic power. NewScientist, http://www.newscientist.com/article/dn23221-first-mindreading-implant-gives-rats-telepathic-power.html. Accessed 8 May 2013

  31. Reardon S (2013) Interspecies telepathy: human thoughts make rats move. NewScientist. http://www.newscientist.com/article/dn23343-interspecies-telepathy-human-thoughts-make-rat-move.html. Accessed 8 May 2013

  32. Adorno TW (1983) Negative dialectics, trans. E. B. Ashton. Continuum, New York, p 148

  33. Marcuse H (1964) One-dimensional man: studies in the ideology of advanced industrial society. Beacon Press, Boston, p 137

  34. Horkheimer M, Adorno TW (2002) Dialectic of enlightenment: philosophical fragments. In: Gunzelin Schmid N (ed) trans. Edmund Jephcott. Stanford University Press, Stanford, p 4

  35. Thacker E (2003) Data made flesh: biotechnology and the discourse of the posthuman. Cultural Critique 53:89

  36. Eunice KY (2005) Britain pro-lifers row over cloning license to Dolly’s father, Christian Today. http://www.christiantoday.com/article/britain.prolifers.row.over.cloning.license.to.dollys.father/2109.htm. Accessed 28 May 2012

  37. Sample I (2010) Craig Venter creates synthetic life form. The Guardian. http://www.guardian.co.uk/science/2010/may/20/craig-venter-synthetic-life-form, Accessed 29 May 2012

  38. Rutherford A (2012) Synthetic biology and the rise of the ‘spider-goats’. http://www.guardian.co.uk/science/2012/jan/14/synthetic-biology-spider-goat-genetics/print. Accessed 29 May 2012

  39. Newell-McGloughlin M, Re E (2006) The evolution of biotechnology: from Natufians to nanotechnology. Springer, Dordrecht, p 52

  40. Sell SK (2007) International institutions, intellectual property, and the HIV/AIDS pandemic. In: Ostergard RL Jr (ed) HIV/AIDS and the threat to national and international security. Palgrave MacMillan, New York, p 151

  41. Murray F (September 2010) The Oncomouse that roared: resistance and accommodation to patenting in academic science. American Journal of Sociology 116:351. doi:10.1086/653599. Accessed 28 May 2012

  42. Linzey A (2002) Genetic engineering. In: Richard S, Morrey JD (eds) Ethical issues in biotechnology. Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham, p 330, Author’s italics

  43. Knight W (2003) Dolly the sheep dies young, New Scientist’. http://www.newscientist.com/article/dn3393-dollythe-sheep-dies-young.html. Accessed 5 June 2012

  44. Shanks N, Greek R (2009) Animal models in light of evolution. BrownWalker Press, Boca Raton, p 310

  45. Best S (1990) Genetic science 10; KarlMarx, Capital Volume 1, trans. Ben Fowkes (London; New York: Penguin Books) 481

  46. Noske B (1997) Beyond boundaries: humans and animals. Black Rose Books, Montreal, p 18

  47. Von Uexküll J (2010) A foray into the worlds of animals and humans with a theory of meaning. In: Cary W (ed) trans. Joseph D. O’Neil, Posthumanities, vol. 12. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, p 43

  48. Merleau-Ponty M (2002) Phenomenology of perception, trans. Colin Smith. Routledge Classics, London; New York, Italics added

  49. Harvey D (1990) The condition of postmodernity: an enquiry into the origins of cultural change. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, Cambridge, p 240

  50. Marinetti FT (1973) The founding and manifesto of futurism 1909. In: Umbro A, Robert B, Flint RW, Higgitt JC, Caroline T (eds) Futurist Manifestos. Thames and Hudson, London, p 22

  51. Virilio P (2007) Speed and politics: an essay on dromology, trans. Mark Polizzotti. Semiotext(e), Los Angeles, p 167

  52. Gigliotti C (2013) “Introduction,” xiv. Italics added. Best, “Genetic Science," 3. Italics added. See also Matthew Cole and Karen Morgan, "Engineering Freedom? A Critique of Biotechnological Routes to Animal Liberation,". Configurations 21:219

  53. Rifkin J (1998) The biotech century: harnessing the gene and remaking the world. Tarcher/Putnam, New York, p 101

  54. Davis K (2011) Procrustean solutions to animal identity and welfare problems. In: Sanbonmatsu J, Gottlieb R (eds) Critical theory and animal liberation, Nature’s Meaning. Boulder: Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham, p 35

  55. “Canadian Environmental Protection Act (1999)” Environment Canada. http://www.ec.gc.ca/lcpe-cepa/default.asp?lang=En&n=24374285-1&offset=1&toc=show. Accessed 5 June 2012

  56. Anthes E (2013) Don’t be afraid of genetic modification. The New York Times. http://www.nytimes.com/2013/03/10/opinion/sunday/dont-be-afraid-of-genetic-modification.html?pagewanted=all&_r=1&. Accessed 10 May 2013

  57. Prather RS, Stumpf TT, Rickords LF (1992) Nuclear transplantation as a method of producing genetically identical livestock. Animal Biotechnology 3:1–67. doi:10.1080/10495399209525763. Accessed 22 Feb 2012

  58. Ferrari A (2006) Genetically modified laboratory animals in the name of the 3Rs? Altex 23:299

  59. Twine R, Stephens N (2013) Introduction to special issue on animal biotechnology: do animal biotechnologies have a latent liberatory imaginary? Configurations 21:130

  60. Rollin BE, Morrey JD (2002) The ‘Frankenstein thing'. In: Richard S (ed) Ethical issues in biotechnology. Rowman and Littlefield, Landham, p 275

  61. Rollin BE (1995) The Frankenstein syndrome: ethical and social issues in the genetic engineering of animals. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, p 171

  62. Robert JS and Baylis F (2003) Crossing species boundaries. The American Journal of Bioethics 3, no. 3 (Summer 2003), 4

  63. Twine R (2010) Genomic natures read through posthumanisms. The Sociological Review 58(1):188

  64. Ferrari A (2012) Animal disenhancement for animal welfare: the apparent philosophical conundrums and the real exploitation of animals. A response to Thompson and Palmer. Nanoethics 6:70

  65. Thompson PB (2008) The opposite of human enhancement: nanotechnology and the blind chicken problem. Nanoethics 2:308

  66. Palmer C (2011) Animal disenhancement and the non-identity problem: a response to Thompson. Nanoethics 5:43–48

  67. Hadley J (2012) Confining ‘disenhanced’ animals. Nanoethics 6:42

  68. Twine R (2013) Is biotechnology deconstructing animal domestication? Movements toward liberation. Configurations 21(2):146

  69. Twine R (2013) Is biotechnology deconstructing animal domestication. 138; 140

  70. Cole M, Morgan K (2011) Engineering freedom? Nanoethics 5:207

  71. Stephens N (2013) Growing meat in laboratories: the promise, ontology, and ethical boundary-work of using muscle cells to make food. Configurations 21(2):167

  72. Joy M (2011) Why we love dogs, eat pigs, and wear cows: an introduction to carnism. Conari Press, San Francisco, pp 96–98

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am deeply indebted to a number of people for their helpful comments and suggestions on this article as it progressed through several drafts, especially Asher Horowitz, John Sanbonmatsu, Will Kymlicka, Sue Donaldson, Christopher Coenen, and Arianna Ferrari. I am also very grateful for the support of the Abby Benjamin Postdoctoral Fellowship Program in Animal Ethics in the Department of Philosophy at Queen’s University.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Zipporah Weisberg.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Weisberg, Z. Biotechnology as End Game: Ontological and Ethical Collapse in the “Biotech Century”. Nanoethics 9, 39–54 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11569-014-0219-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11569-014-0219-5

Keywords

Navigation