Skip to main content
Log in

Reply to Professor Klosko

  • Reply
  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. See Cohen (1989, p. 734, n. 23).

  2. The phrase ‘stably just’ is Cohen’s; see Cohen (1989, p. 744).

  3. The phrase ‘intrinsically stable’ occurs at Rawls (1999a, p. 106).

  4. Another way to describe Rawls’s accomplishment would be to say that he has (1) designed a contract situation in which intuitively plausible distributive principles would be agreed to and (2) shown that the agreement reached in that situation would be self-enforcing. I take this accomplishment to be significant because the problem of designing self-enforcing agreements which implement socially optimal outcomes in important cases is a decidedly non-trivial problem. I consider this way of characterizing Rawls’s accomplishment in Weithman (2015).

  5. For a rigorous and imaginative argument for the possibility of the former, see Kavka (1983).

  6. See also Rawls (1999a, p. 106).

  7. Rawls says of Kant ‘In his moral philosophy, Kant seeks self-knowledge’ (Rawls 2000, p. 148). I believe he would say the same of himself.

  8. See Rawls (2000, pp. 319–320) where Rawls says that Kant thought history aroused ‘loathing for our species.’

  9. See, for example, Niebuhr (1986, pp. 123–141). Though Niebuhr did not, of course, know Rawls’s work, he is quite critical of the overly optimistic view of humanity that he thinks Enlightenment liberalism assumes.

  10. According to data compiled by the UN, Sweden has the lowest Gini coefficient of income, and hence the least income inequality, among the advanced democracies (https://data.undp.org/dataset/Income-Gini-coefficient/36ku-rvrj). This fact, when conjoined with Sweden’s high level of human development, might suggest that it satisfies or comes close to satisfying the difference principle. But even if it does, Sweden would seem to need ‘wholesale change’ to satisfy the demands of fair equality of opportunity as measured by social mobility; see Clark (2014, pp. 19–44).

  11. For example, see Gaus (2015).

  12. For a vivid statement of how the comparison works, see (Laden 1991, pp. 189–222, p. 212).

  13. Of course, one might disagree with Rawls and argue that it is inherent stability which is irrelevant to the choice of principles, either because one thinks that stability of any kind is irrelevant to the demands of justice (as Cohen 2008 argues) or because one thinks (as Professor Klosko seems to) that some other kind of stability is relevant instead. But those are arguments that would need to be made.

  14. See, for example, Gilley (2006, p. 499).

References

  • Clark, Gregory. 2014. The son also rises. London: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Gerald A. 2008. Rescuing justice and equality. London: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Joshua. 1989. Democratic equality. Ethics 99: 727–751.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, Gerald. 2015. The egalitarian species. Social Philosophy and Policy 31: 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilley, Bruce. 2006. The meaning and measure of state legitimacy: Results for 72 countries. European Journal of Political Research 45: 499–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hampton, Jean. 1986. Hobbes and the social contract tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kavka, Gregory. 1983. Rule by fear. Noûs 17: 601–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kavka, Gregory. 1986. Hobbesian moral and political theory. London: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klosko, George. 2015. ‘Rawls, Weithman, and the Stability of Liberal Democracy’. Res Publica. doi:10.1007/s11158-015-9286-x.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laden, Anthony. 1991. Games, Fairness, and Rawls's a theory of justice. Philosophy & Public Affairs 20(3): 189–222.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David. 1979. Prisoners’ dilemma is a newcomb problem. Philosophy & Public Affairs 8: 235–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1986. Augustine’s political realism. In The essential reinhold niebuhr, ed. Robert McAfee Brown. London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1996. Political liberalism. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1999a. In Collected papers, ed. Samuel Freeman, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Rawls, John. 1999b. The law of peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1999c. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 2000. In Lectures on the history of moral philosophy, ed. Barbara Herman, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Rawls, John. 2001. Justice as fairness: A restatement. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 2007. In Lectures on the history of political philosophy, ed. Samuel Freeman, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Weithman, Paul. 2010. Why political liberalism?. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weithman, Paul. 2015. Relational stability, inherent stability, and the reach of contractualism. Social Philosophy and Policy 31: 92–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Paul Weithman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Weithman, P. Reply to Professor Klosko. Res Publica 21, 251–264 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-015-9288-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-015-9288-8

Keywords

Navigation