Skip to main content
Log in

Power and activity: a dynamic do-over*

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Powers theorists frequently assert that their neo-Aristotelian frameworks are dynamic, and that this gives them a theoretical advantage over their neo-Humean rivals. But recently it’s been claimed that activity can also be used to divide powers theories themselves. Dynamism is here understood primarily in terms of activity: a metaphysic counts as dynamic according to the place activity is given within the system. Activists treat activity as fundamental or irreducible, and claim to have the philosophical high ground over those ‘passivist’ powers theories wherein activity is reducible or nonfundamental.

In this paper I take a closer look at dynamism within powers theories, with a particular focus on how the activism/passivism distinction might be made. I then consider the broader ontological impact that the various commitments to activity might carry, along with an assessment as to who appears to be better off. Despite what’s been claimed, I find no reason to think that activists have any serious theoretical advantage in this debate. In fact, as things presently stand, I am not convinced that powers and activity make for a good pairing at all, as there’s presently no good model for powers like this.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data Availability

The author confirms that all primary and secondary sources and data supporting the findings of this study were either publicly available at the time of submission or accessible to those with electronic library access.

Notes

  1. Talk of worlds as “cold” and “dead” is used by Ellis (2001: 107) as a colourful criticism of neo-Humean metaphysics. He takes the phrase from Burtt (1932), who himself offered it as an unflattering description of seventeenth century mechanism. It has since been employed by dynamically-inclined powers theorists against their less dynamic neighbours, often with the explicit addition that they see the latter’s view of the world as resembling neo-Humeanism.

  2. Groff (2021, 2013) is the most conspicuous advocate of this position, but similar sentiments are present in Meincke (2020, 2018); Mumford and Anjum (2011, 2018), Cartwright (2007). According to Groff (2021: 9890), activism is the majority view among powers theorists.

  3. Groff (2021) contrasts passivism with “anti-passivism”. I much prefer the use of ‘activism’.

  4. Part of the claim to the high ground seems to come from the suggestion that passivism is too close to neo-Humeanism to capture what is wanted or desirable about powers metaphysics in general. The degree to which a view is similar to those held by Humeans is not, in my estimation, any indicator of its truth or success.

  5. Backmann (2019: 980)

  6. Meincke (2020: 101) offers these claims as an analysis of Mumford and Anjum’s dynamism. And though she is highly sympathetic to their approach, her own dynamism is somewhat more radical, more in keeping with Dupre’s views (see Sect. 5).

  7. Bird (2007) is accused of treating activities as merely metaphorical, but his text is littered with examples of processes about which he seems genuinely serious. I suspect they are more than just metaphorical, even if they are reducible.

  8. Though Groff and Meincke give quite specific versions of the activist/passivist distinction, I have opted for a somewhat more flexible approach so as to cast a wider net.

  9. For just a few of the many examples, see Mumford and Anjum (2011), Groff (2021: 9892), Williams (2019), Backmann (2019), Roselli and Austin (2021), Giannini (2022).

  10. Williams (2019: 13).

  11. I am assuming that the desiderata include something along the lines of explaining causation and or modality by appeal to internal features of objects.

  12. Pace Giannini (2022). Giannini distinguishes between what he calls ‘moderate’ and ‘radical’ powers theories, denying that production is a feature of the former. However, I read him as understanding production in a production-cum-activity way, and so our disagreement might only be superficial.

  13. Backmann (2019); Donati (2018). See also Friebe (2018).

  14. Giannini (2022).

  15. Roselli (2022).

  16. Unless, of course, the claim isn’t that production-plus-eternalism isn’t incompatible, but merely less desirable than production-plus-substantial present.

  17. As one referee notes, the suggestion that passivists treat activities as identical with flip-books is wildly uncharitable. Even if the temporal parts are the only fundamental material constituents of activities, the story doesn’t end there. As Epstein (2015) argues, there’s no more to the ontology of ant colonies than ants, but the right story can’t be given in terms of ants alone: they stand in complicated relations and roles that impose social structures, even if ants comprise all the stuff. On the powers theory, genuine activities require causal connections. Other passivist metaphysics will impose other rules, lest we lose the ability to distinguish causal processes from pseudo-processes. See Williams (2021).

  18. Though largely about reduction, we need to include fundamentality in the distinction to rule out cases in which activities are reducible to collections of temporal parts but the parts are not ontologically prior to the activities. Furthermore, though parts alone are not sufficient for even passivist activities, if activists eschew them, that is distinction enough.

  19. Giannini (2022: 2816) points to this dimension of activism.

  20. Builes (2022).

  21. Rosen (2010).

  22. Composition is not restricted to parts of the same nature, so activities can be formed out of the entities that serve as the ersatz past and present, despite the peculiarity. By contrast, we can’t take that composite activity as fundamental and then abstract parts from it, as the activist would need to do to keep pace with the passivist.

  23. Tooley (1997); Cameron (2015).

  24. For non-instantaneous temporal parts, see Lewis (1983), Heller (1990), Zimmerman (1996) and Williams (2017).

  25. Mumford and Anjum (2011: 116).

  26. This is not an explanation of change, just an analysis. It’s so minimal I’d be hard pressed to make sense of anyone who rejected it.

  27. Both Dupre (2021) and Meincke (2020) reconceptualize objects as stable patterns of processes.

  28. Thinking about powers in the context of activism, Groff (2020: 29) states that “Powers, in so far as they are properties, are abstractions.”

  29. Donati (2018).

  30. If we assume that the change it undergoes is due to some power interaction at the start, then why would it not react with other powers over the process it spans? And if it does, aren’t we just back to the same problem again? A series of states handles this nicely.

  31. For more on immanent and transuent causation within a powers framework, see Williams (2019: ch. 7).

  32. Dupre (2021: 10,669).

  33. Mumford and Anjum (2011). Though there are putatively other accounts in the literature, such as Heil (2012) and Dupre (2021), most never go beyond offering further examples of activities. The serious content is negative, largely objecting to neo-Humean accounts, and resorting to metaphors in which the interaction of processes is some sort of swirling, changing, thing, like the intertwined strands of DNA or the rainbow colours of an oil slick.

  34. It’s worth repeating that I’m attempting to employ the vector model in ways for which it wasn’t intended. It’s thus no knock against it should it fail.

  35. Marmodoro (2020: 63).

  36. These remarks are in keeping with suggestions recently made by Meincke (2018, 2020). Like me, she thinks that much more investigation into activism is needed, and is skeptical that the right way forward will resemble those already explored.

  37. Special thanks to audiences at the Change and Change-Makers conference and the SoCal Metaphysics Workshop for discussion of earlier drafts of this paper, and to two anonymous referees for their comments.

References

  • Backmann, M. (2019). No time for powers. Inquiry, 62, 979–1007.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and properties. Oxford University Press.

  • Builes, D. (2022). Derivatives and consciousness. The Journal of Consciousness Studies, 27, 87–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burtt, E. A. (1932). Metaphysical foundations of Modern Science (2nd ed.). Routledge.

  • Cameron, R. (2015). The moving spotlight: An essay on Time and Ontology. Oxford University Press.

  • Cartwright, N. (2007). Hunting causes and using them: Approaches in philosophy and economics. Cambridge University Press.

  • Donati, D. (2018). No time for Powers. PhD Diss. University of Nottingham.

  • Dupre, J. (2021). Causally powerful processes. Synthese, 199, 10667–10683.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge University Press.

  • Epstein, B. (2015). The ant trap. Cambridge University Press.

  • Friebe, C. (2018). Metaphysics of laws and ontology of Time. THEORIA, 33, 77–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giannini, G. (2022). Powers, processes, and Time. ” Erkenntnis, 87, 2801–2825.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Groff, R. (2013). “Whose Powers? Which Agency?” Powers and Capacities in Philosophy: The New Aristotelianism, Groff and Greco (eds.). Springer: 207–228.

  • Groff, R. (2020). “What Does the Doing? On Powers, Things, and Powerful Things”. Dispositionalism—Perspectives from Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science, Meincke, AS (ed.). Springer: 27–40.

  • Groff, R. (2021). Conceptualizing Causal Powers: Activity, Capacity, Essence, Necessitation. Synthese, 199, 9881–9896.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. (2012). The Universe as we find it. Oxford University Press.

  • Heller, M. (1990). The ontology of physical objects—four-dimensional Hunks of Matter. Cambridge University Press.

  • Lewis, D. (1983). “Survival and Identity”. Philosophical Papers Vol 1 Oxford University Press: 55–77.

  • Marmodoro, A. (2020). “Powers, Activity and Interaction”. Dispositionalism—Perspectives from Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science, Meincke, AS (ed.). Springer: 55–66.

  • Meincke, A. S. (2018). “Persons as Biological Processes: A Bio-Processual Way out of the Personal Identity Dilemma”. Everything Flows Nicholson, DJ and Dupre, J (eds.) Oxford University Press: 357 – 78.

  • Meincke, A. S. (2020). “Powers, Persistence and Process”. Dispositionalism—Perspectives from Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science, Meincke, AS (ed.). Springer: 89–114.

  • Mumford, S., & Anjum, R. (2011). Getting causes from Powers. Oxford University Press.

  • Mumford, S., & Anjum, R. (2018). What tends to be. Oxford University Press.

  • Roselli, A. (2022). Dispositional essentialism in the Eternalist Block. Powers, Time and Free Will (pp. 51–68). Austin.

  • Roselli, A., & Austin, C. (2021). The Dynamical Essence of Powers. Synthese, 199, 14951–14973.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (2010). “Metaphysical Dependence: Grounding and Reduction”. Modality: Metaphysics, Logic and Epistemology. Hale and Hoffman (eds.) Oxford: 109–135.

  • Tooley, M. (1997). Time, Tense, and Causation. Oxford University Press.

  • Williams, N. E. (2017). Powerful perdurance: Linking parts with Powers. In J. Jacobs (Ed.), Causal Powers (pp. 139–164). Oxford University Press.

  • Williams, N. E. (2019). The Powers Metaphysic. Oxford University Press.

  • Williams, N. E. (2021). (a New Paradigm for) the Problem of the many. Synthese, 199, 5533–5550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, D. (1996). Persistence and Presentism Philosophical Papers. 25.

Download references

Funding

This work was not conducted under any special funding.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

The author (Neil E Williams) is the sole author of the article.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Neil E Williams.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares that they have no known competing financial interests or personal relationships that could have appeared to influence the work reported in this paper.

Ethics approval and consent to participate

The author declares that the manuscript is the authors’ own original work, and has not been previously published elsewhere. The manuscript is not currently being considered for publication elsewhere. The paper reflects the authors? own research and the results are appropriately placed in the context of prior and existing research.

Consent for publication

All sources used are properly disclosed.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

* The title makes use of the informal americanism ‘do-over’, which is akin to a second attempt at something, not the informal british ‘do over’, meaning to beat someone up.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Williams, N.E. Power and activity: a dynamic do-over*. Philos Stud (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-023-02032-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-023-02032-3

Keywords

Navigation