Skip to main content
Log in

On the characterizations of viable proposals

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Sengupta and Sengupta (Int Econ Rev 35:347–359, 1994) consider a payoff configuration of a TU game as a viable proposal if it challenges each legitimate contender. Lauwers (Int Econ Rev 43:1369–1371, 2002) prove that the set of viable proposals is nonempty for every game. In the present paper, we prove that the set of viable proposals coincides with the coalition structure core if there exists an undominated proposal; otherwise, it coincides with the set of accessible proposals. This characterization result implies that a proposal is a viable proposal if and only if it is undominated or accessible. Moreover, we prove that the set of viable proposals includes the minimal dominant set, which is another nonempty extension of the coalition structure core introduced by Kóczy and Lauwers (Games Econ Behav 61:277–298, 2007). In particular, we prove that the set of viable proposals of a cohesive game coincides with the minimal dominant set.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, the coalition structure core of the game derived from the labor market by Kelso and Crawford (1982) might be empty when workers are not substitutes for each other.

  2. For details of the results, please see Greenberg (1994).

  3. Note that the coalition structure core collects undominated proposals.

  4. In contrast to our proof, Lauwers’ (2002) proof for the existence of viable proposal is based on a topological approach.

  5. The intuition of Theorem 2 (a) is due to Kóczy and Lauwers (2004), but we state the result here to contrast it with the result of Theorem 2 (b).

  6. Henceforth, we will refer to this result as the Kóczy-Lauwers Theorem.

  7. The result of Theorem 3 is an analogue of Theorem 10 in Yang (2012), which shows that when the core is a singleton, the unique undominated imputation is the only accessible imputation, i.e., an imputation that can be reached from any other imputation through a sequence of dominating imputations.

References

  • Aumann, R. J., & Drèze, J. H. (1974). Cooperative games with coalition structures. International Journal of Game Theory, 3, 217–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Béal, S., Rémila, E., & Solal, P. (2012). On the number of blocks required to access the core. Discrete Applied Mathematics, 160, 925–932.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Béal, S., Rémila, E., & Solal, P. (2013a). Accessibility and stability of the coalition structure core. Mathematical Methods of Operations Research, 78, 187–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Béal, S., Rémila, E., & Solal, P. (2013b). An optimal bound to access the core in TU-games. Games and Economic Behavior, 80, 1–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bejan, C., & Gómez, J. C. (2009). Core extensions for non-balanced TU-games. International Journal of Game Theory, 38, 3–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bhattacharya, A., & Ziad, A. (2006). The core as the set of eventually stable outcomes: A note. Games and Economic Behavior, 54, 25–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bondareva, O. N. (1963). Some applications of the methods of linear programming to the theory of cooperative games (Russian). Problemy Kibernetiki, 10, 119–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg, J. (1994). Chapter 37: Coalition structures. In R. J. Aumann & S. Hart (Eds.), Handbook of game theory with economic applications (Vol. II, pp. 1305–1307). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, A. S., & Crawford, V. P. (1982). Job matching, coalition formation, and gross substitutes. Econometrica, 50, 1483–1504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kóczy, L. Á. (2006). The core can be accessed with a bounded number of blocks. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 43, 56–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kóczy, L. Á., & Lauwers, L. (2004). The coalition structure core is accessible. Games and Economic Behavior, 48, 86–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kóczy, L. Á., & Lauwers, L. (2007). The minimal dominant set is a nonempty core-extension. Games and Economic Behavior, 61, 277–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauwers, L. (2002). A note on viable proposals. International Economic Review, 43, 1369–1371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maschler, M., Peleg, B., & Shapley, L. S. (1979). Geometric properties of the kernel, nucleolus, and related solution concepts. Mathematics of Operations Research, 4, 303–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sengupta, A., & Sengupta, K. (1994). Viable proposals. International Economic Review, 35, 347–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sengupta, A., & Sengupta, K. (1996). A property of the core. Games and Economic Behavior, 12, 266–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapley, L. S. (1967). On balanced sets and cores. Naval Research Logistics Quarterly, 14, 453–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yang, Y. Y. (2010). On the accessibility of the core. Games and Economic Behavior, 69, 194–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yang, Y. Y. (2012). On the accessibility of core-extensions. Games and Economic Behavior, 74, 687–698.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yi-You Yang.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

The author is very grateful to two anonymous referees for their perceptive comments of the paper.

Appendix: Proof of Proposition 1

Appendix: Proof of Proposition 1

Proof of Proposition 1

(a) Let \((x,\mathcal {P})\in \Omega (N,v)\) be any given proposal. Since \(C(N,v)=\emptyset \), by the Bondareva-Shapley Theorem, it follows that

$$\begin{aligned} \underset{S\in \mathcal {B}}{\sum }\lambda _{S} v(S) > \underset{S\in \mathcal {P}}{\sum }v(S) =x(N) =\underset{S\in \mathcal {B}}{\sum }\lambda _{S}x(S). \end{aligned}$$

Hence, we have \(\sum _{S\in \mathcal {B}}\lambda _S[v(S)-x(S)]>0\). Combining with the fact that \(\lambda _S>0\) for all \(S\in \mathcal {B}\), we have that there exists a coalition \(T\in \mathcal {B}\) such that \(v(T) >x(T)\). Moreover, since \(x(T)\ge \sum _{i\in T}v(\{i\})\), we have \(|T|\ge 2\).

(b) Let \(T\in \mathcal {B}\) be a coalition with \(|T|\ge 2\). It suffices to prove that the core of the subgame \((T, v_{T})\) is nonempty. Suppose, to the contrary, that the core of \((T,v_T)\) is empty. Then there exists a T-balanced collection \(\mathcal {B}'\) with balancing weights \(\{\lambda '_{S}\} _{S\in \mathcal {B}'}\) satisfying \(\sum \nolimits _{S\in \mathcal {B}'}\lambda '_{S}v_{T}(S)>v_{T}(T).\) This implies

$$\begin{aligned} \sum \limits _{S\in \mathcal {B}'}\lambda _{T} \lambda ' _{S} v(S) +\sum \limits _{S\in \mathcal {B}\backslash \{T\} }\lambda _{S} v(S)>\sum \limits _{S\in \mathcal {B}}\lambda _{S}v( S). \end{aligned}$$

However, this is impossible since \(\mathcal {B}'\cup (\mathcal {B}\backslash \{T\})\) is an N-balanced collection with balancing weights \(\{ \lambda _T \lambda '_{S}\}_{S\in \mathcal {B}'}\cup \{\lambda _{S}\}_{S\in \mathcal {B}\backslash \{ T\}}\). Hence, the core of \((T, v_{T})\) is nonempty.

(c) Let \((x_0,\mathcal {P}_0)\in \Omega (N,v)\) be any given proposal. To prove that \((x,\mathcal {R}(T))\) is accessible from \((x_0,\mathcal {P}_0)\), we inductively construct a sequence of proposals

$$\begin{aligned} (x_0,\mathcal {P}_0)\rightarrow _{T_1} (x_1,\mathcal {P}_1)\rightarrow _{T_2} \cdots \rightarrow _{T_{j}} (x_j,\mathcal {P}_j)\rightarrow _{T_{j+1}} \cdots , \end{aligned}$$
(4)

where \(T_k\in \mathcal {B}\) for \(k=1,2,\ldots \), and prove that sequence (4) does terminate at \((x,\mathcal {R}(T))\).

Suppose that the sequence of proposals \(\{(x_k,\mathcal {P}_k)\}_{k=0}^j\) has been constructed to satisfy \((x_{k-1},\mathcal {P}_{k-1})\rightarrow _{T_k} (x_k,\mathcal {P}_k)\) with \(T_k\in \mathcal {B}\) for \(k=1,\ldots ,j\). Let \(A_k=\{i\in T:x_k^i>v(\{i\})\}\) for \(k=0,\ldots ,j\). We first assume that \(A_j=\emptyset \), i.e., \(x_j^i=v(\{i\})\) for \(i\in T\). Since \((T,v_T)\) is cohesive, it follows that \(v(T)>\sum _{i\in T}v(\{i\})=x_j(T)\), and hence \((x,\mathcal {R}(T))\) dominates \((x_j,\mathcal {P}_j)\) by T. This implies that \((x,\mathcal {R}(T))\) is accessible from \((x_0,\mathcal {P}_0)\) and we are done.

In what follows, we assume that \(A_j\ne \emptyset \). By (a), there exists a proposal \(T_{j+1}\in \mathcal {B}\) such that \(v(T_{j+1})>x_j(T_{j+1})\). Let \(\mathcal {P}_{j+1}=\mathcal {R}(T_{j+1})\). We consider three cases.

Case I. \(T_{j+1}\cap A_j \ne \emptyset \). Let \((x_{j+1},\mathcal {P}_{j+1})\in \Omega (N,v)\) be the proposal defined by

$$\begin{aligned} x_{j+1}^i= {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} x_j^i+[v(T_{j+1})-x_j(T_{j+1})]/|T_{j+1}\cap A_j|,&{} \text {if } i\in T_{j+1}\cap A_j,\\ x_j^i, &{}\quad \text {if } i\in T_{j+1}\backslash A_j,\\ v(\{i\}),&{}\quad \text {otherwise.} \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$

Clearly, \((x_{j+1},\mathcal {P}_{j+1})\) dominates \((x_j,\mathcal {P}_j)\) by \(T_{j+1}\). Let \(A_{j+1}=\{i\in T:x_{j+1}^i>v(\{i\})\}\). Then we have \( A_{j}\supseteq T_{j+1}\cap A_j=A_{j+1}\ne \emptyset \).

Case II. \(T_{j+1}\cap A_j =\emptyset \) and \(T_{j+1}\backslash T \ne \emptyset \). Let \((x_{j+1},\mathcal {P}_{j+1})\in \Omega (N,v)\) be the proposal defined by

$$\begin{aligned} x_{j+1}^i= {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} x_j^i+[v(T_{j+1})-x_j(T_{j+1})]/|T_{j+1}\backslash T|,&{}\quad \text {if } i\in T_{j+1}\backslash T,\\ x_j^i=v(\{i\}), &{}\quad \quad \text {if } i\in T_{j+1}\cap T,\\ v(\{i\}),&{}\quad \text {otherwise.} \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$

Again, one can easily check that \((x_{j+1},\mathcal {P}_{j+1})\) dominates \((x_j,\mathcal {P}_j)\) by \(T_{j+1}\). Let \(A_{j+1}=\{i\in T:x_{j+1}^i>v(\{i\})\}\). Then we have \(A_{j+1}=\emptyset \). This implies that \((x,\mathcal {R}(T))\) dominates \((x_{j+1},\mathcal {P}_{j+1})\) by T and we are done.

Case III. \(T_{j+1}\cap A_j =\emptyset \) and \(T_{j+1}\subseteq T\). Let \(\lambda =\frac{v(T_{j+1})-x_j(T_{j+1})}{x(T_{j+1})-x_j(T_{j+1})}\). Since \(x(T_{j+1})\ge v(T_{j+1})>x_j(T_{j+1})\), it follows that \(1\ge \lambda >0\). Let \((x_{j+1},\mathcal {P}_{j+1})\in \Omega (N,v)\) be the proposal defined by

$$\begin{aligned} x_{j+1}^i= {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} x_j^i+\lambda (x^i-x_j^i),&{}\quad \text {if } i\in T_{j+1},\\ v(\{i\}),&{}\quad \text {otherwise}, \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$

where \(x^i_j=v(\{i\})\) for each \(i\in T_{j+1}\). Clearly, \((x_{j+1},\mathcal {P}_{j+1})\) dominates \((x_j,\mathcal {P}_j)\) by \(T_{j+1}\) and \(x^i\ge x_{j+1}^i\) for each \(i\in T_{j+1}\). Moreover, since \(A_j\ne \emptyset \) and \(T_{j+1}\cap A_j=\emptyset \), it follows that \(T_{j+1}\ne T\). By the fact that \((T,v_T)\) is cohesive, we have \(v(T)>v(T_{j+1})+\sum _{i\in T\backslash T_{j+1}}v(\{i\})\). This implies that \((x,\mathcal {R}(T))\) dominates \((x_{j+1},\mathcal {P}_{j+1})\) by T and we are done.

Suppose, to the contrary, that the construction of sequence (4) does not come to an end. Let \(a_k=x_k(A_k)\) for \(k=0,1,2,\ldots \). Since the corresponding sequence

$$\begin{aligned} A_0\supseteq T_1\cap A_0=A_1\supseteq \cdots A_j\supseteq T_{j+1}\cap A_j=A_{j+1}\supseteq \cdots \end{aligned}$$

is weakly decreasing, there exists a non-negative integer r such that \(A_r\ne \emptyset \) and \(A_r=A_{r+t}\) for \(t=1,2,\ldots \). This implies that \(A_r\subseteq T_{r+t}\) for \(t=1,2,\ldots \), and the sequence \(a_r<a_{r+1}<a_{r+2}<\cdots \) is strictly increasing. Moreover, since the number of coalitions in \(\mathcal {B}\) is finite, there exists a positive integer \(t^*\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} \bigcap _{t=1}^{\infty } T_{r+t}=\bigcap _{t=1}^{t^*} T_{r+t}\supseteq A_r \end{aligned}$$
(5)

and there exist two distinct positive integers \(k_1<k_2\) such that \(T_{r+t^*+k_1}=T_{r+t^*+k_2}\). By (5), we have that

$$\begin{aligned} x^i_{r+t^*+k_1}=x^i_{r+t^*+k_2}= {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} x_{r+t^*}^i,&{}\quad \text {if } i\in \left( \bigcap _{t=1}^{t^*} T_{r+t}\right) \backslash A_r,\\ v(\{i\}),&{} \quad \text {if } i\in N\backslash \left( \bigcap _{t=1}^{t^*} T_{r+t}\right) . \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$

This implies

$$\begin{aligned} a_{r+t^*+k_1}&=x_{r+t^*+k_1}(A_{r+t^*+k_1})=x_{r+t^*+k_1}(A_r)=v(T_{r+t^*+k_1})-x_{r+t^*+k_1}(T_{r+t^*+k_1}\backslash A_r)\\&=v(T_{r+t^*+k_2})-x_{r+t^*+k_2}(T_{r+t^*+k_2}\backslash A_r)=x_{r+t^*+k_2}(A_r)=a_{r+t^*+k_2}, \end{aligned}$$

contradicting the fact \(a_{r+t^*+k_1}<a_{r+t^*+k_2}\). \(\square \)

To better illustrate the iterative process for generating a dominating chain that terminates at an accessible proposal in the proof of Proposition 1 (c), it can be useful to consider the following example.

Example 3

Consider the three-player game (Nv) given by

$$\begin{aligned} v(\{1,2,3\})&=v(\{1,2\})=v(\{1,3\})=v(\{2,3\})=3,\\ v(\{1\})&=v(\{2\})=v(\{3\})=0. \end{aligned}$$

Let \(T_1=\{1,2\},T_2=\{1,3\},T_3=\{2,3\}\). Clearly, \(\mathcal {B}=\{T_1,T_2,T_3\}\) is an N-balanced collection with balancing weights \(\lambda _1=\lambda _2=\lambda _3=1/2\) that maximizes the amount \(\sum _{S\in \mathcal {B}}\lambda _Sv(S)\) and \((T_j,v_{T_j})\) is cohesive for \(j=1,2,3\). Since

$$\begin{aligned} v^*=\max _{\mathcal {P}\in \Pi }\sum _{S\in \mathcal {P}}v(S)=v(\{1,2\})+v(\{3\})=3<9/2=\sum _{j=1}^3\lambda _jv(T_j), \end{aligned}$$

by the Bondareva–Shapley Theorem, it follows that \(C(N,v)=\emptyset \). One can verify that the iterative process in the proof of Proposition 1 (c) generates a dominating chain from \((x_0,\mathcal {P}_0)=(1,1,1,N)\) to \((x,\mathcal {R}(T_3))=(0,1,2,\{2,3\},\{1\})\) with the associated decreasing sequence \(A_0=\{2,3\}\supseteq T_1\cap A_0=A_1=\{2\}\supseteq T_2\cap A_1=\emptyset \) as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} (1,1,1,N)\rightarrow _{T_1} (1,2,0,\{1,2\},\{3\})\rightarrow _{T_2}(3,0,0,\{1,3\},\{2\})\rightarrow _{T_3}(0,1,2,\{2,3\},\{1\}). \end{aligned}$$

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Yang, YY. On the characterizations of viable proposals. Theory Decis 89, 453–469 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-020-09762-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-020-09762-4

Keywords

Navigation