Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Republican Responsibility in Criminal Law

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Criminal Law and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Retributivism so dominates criminal theory that lawyers, legal scholars and law students assert with complete confidence that criminal law is justified only in light of violations of another person’s rights. Yet the core tenet of retributivism views criminal law fundamentally through the lens of individual actors, rendering both offender and victim unrecognizably denuded from their social and civic context. Doing so means that retributivism is unable to explain even our most basic criminal law practices, such as why we punish recidivists more than first time offenders or why “hate crimes” are of special concern. A republican view of criminal law brings our most natural intuitions back into focus by insisting that the core of criminal responsibility lies in the offender’s attack on the civic bonds that make living in a society as equals possible. By grounding our punishment practices in an Aristotelian republicanism that for so long was the unquestioned basis of mutual responsibility, we understand that hostility, as expressed in the offender’s “civic character,” matters to us all while still seeing our obligations to reintegrate both victim and offender into our shared civic project.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The chief rival to retributivism, consequentialism, is most powerfully embarrassed by the inability to appropriately restrict criminal law in principle. The classic thought experiment undermines the consequentialist by imagining a situation where harm to a large group of people can be avoided by framing and “punishing” an innocent person for a crime he did not commit. That consequentialism does not provide a principled reason not to punish in such cases means its advocates must either deny that such a scenario is plausible, import foreign deontological constraints (Rawls 1955) or bite the bullet and admit that inflicting punishment on innocent persons for the sake of increased utility is morally acceptable (Smart 1973). In any case, the lack of intrinsic limits on the reach of state power lands a deep blow to the plausibility of consequentialism as a political theory.

  2. Indeed, I have elsewhere argued for a rejection of character-based theories of criminal law based on stringent liberal deontological grounds (Yankah 2004; Yankah 2009).

  3. Trayvon Martin was a 17-year old African-American, fatally shot by George Zimmerman, a multi-racial Hispanic man who was appointed the neighborhood watch coordinator in the gated community where Martin was staying. Zimmerman noticed Martin and felt the young, African-American man was behaving suspiciously. He contacted the police, who instructed him not to interact with Martin and informed him they were en route. Despite this Zimmerman approached Martin and the encounter ended with Zimmerman shooting Martin, once in the chest.

    When the police arrived, Zimmerman, bleeding from the nose and lacerations on the back of his head, claimed that Martin had attacked him. Though questioned for 5 h Zimmerman was not arrested or charged with a crime. For many in the African-American community, the decision not to charge Zimmerman was evidence that police acquiesced in the social image that young, black men could be treated as a constant threat and in any case the life of a young black man was of less value.

  4. Whether this accurately captures Kant’s views on legal punishment is a matter of much greater controversy. On the best reading of Kant it is at least severely incomplete as it ignores the important inconsistencies in Kant’s ambivalent musings on punishment and the fact that the basis of legal power in the Rechtslehre is securing equal freedom rather than punishing internal moral blameworthiness. See Murphy (1987); Ripstein (2009 ).

  5. Some philosophers have famously tried to find space in liberalism for a sort of perfectionism. Raz (1986 ).

  6. Other scholars balance the retributivist impulse to punish against a rigorous deontological view of rights as against state interference in order to cabin modern excesses of criminal punishment. See Husak (2008).

  7. Bureau of Justice Assistance, Dep't of Justice, National Assessment of Structured Sentencing 71, 341–352 (1996).

  8. U.S. Sentencing Comm'n, U.S. Sentencing Guidelines Manual § 4A, introductory cmt. (2008).

  9. George Fletcher, for example, once held that it was the ability to attribute a criminal act to the offender’s character that grounded liability and provided an explanation of the nature of excusing conditions. Fletcher (1978 : 799–802). Jeremy Horder has indicated the same. Horder (2007). For a fuller discussion of character theories of law see Yankah (2004).

  10. Here I bracket Hurd and Moore’s arguments that hate crime legislation is unique in inculpating greater punishment for motive.

  11. For an engaging discussion of the ways in which hate crime legislation may not be particularly unique in inspecting motivation and may cause distinct harm see Kim (2006).

References

  • Abel, J.A. (2005), Americans Under Attack: The Need for Federal Hate Crime Legislation in Light of Post-September 11 Attacks on Arab Americans and Muslims; 12 Asian L.J. 41.

  • Aristotle (1941a). Politica. In R. McKeon (Ed.), The basic works of Aristotle.

  • Aristotle (1941b). Nicomachean Ethics. In R. McKeon (Ed.), The basic works of Aristotle.

  • Bagaric, M. (2000) Double Punishment and Punishing Character: The Unfairness of Prior Convictions, 19 Crim. Just. Ethics 10

  • Braithwaite, J. and Pettit, P. (1990), Not Just Deserts: A Republican Theory of Criminal Law

  • Cooper, J. (2005). Political Animals and Civic Friendship. In R Kraut & S. Skultety (eds.), Aristotle’s Politics: Critical Essays.

  • Dubber, M.D. (2001) Policing Possession: The War on Crime and the End of Criminal Law, 91 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 829

  • Duff, R.A. (1993) Choice, Character, and Criminal Liability, 12 Law & Phil. 345

  • Duff, R.A. (2001), Punishment, Communication, and Community

  • Duff, R.A. (2002) Virtue, Vice, and Criminal Liability: Do We Want an Aristotelian Criminal Law?, 6 Buff. Crim. L. Rev. 147

  • Duff, R.A. (2007), Answering for Crime

  • Duff, R.A. (2013) Responsibility, Citizenship, and Criminal Law in In R.A. Duff & S. Green (Eds.) Philosophical Foundations of Criminal Law.

  • Duff, R.A. and Marshall, S. (2010) Public and Private Wrongs, in James Chalmers et al. (eds.), Essays in Criminal Law in Honour of Sir Gerald Gordon

  • Edmundson, W.A. (2006), The Virtue of Law-Abidance; 6 Philosopher’s Imprint 1

  • Fagan, J (2014), The Indignities of Order Maintenance Policing (forthcoming)

  • Fletcher, G.P. (1978) Rethinking Criminal Law

  • Fletcher, G.P. (1982) The Recidivist Premium, 1 Crim. Just. Ethics 54

  • Gargarella, R. (2009). Tough on punishment: Criminal justice, deliberation, and legal alienation. In S Besson & J. L. Martí (Eds.) Legal republicanism: National and international perspectives (Vol. 184).

  • Green, S.P. (2006) Lying, Cheating, and Stealing: A Moral Theory of White-Collar Crime

  • Harel, A. & Parchomovsky, G. (1999) On Hate and Equality, 109 Yale L.J. 507.

  • Horder, J (2007), Excusing Crime

  • Hurd, H and Moore, M.S. (2004), Punishing Hatred and Prejudice, 56 Stanford Law Review 1081

  • Husak, D. (2008), Overcriminalization: The Limits of Criminal Law

  • Kahan, D.M. (1997) Ignorance of Law is an Excuse: But only for the Virtuous, 96 Mich. L. Rev. 127

  • Kant, I (1996), The Metaphysics of Morals (Ed. Mary Gregor)

  • Kim, J.Y. (2006) Hate Crime Law and the Limits of Inculpation, 84 Neb. L. Rev. 846

  • Kraut, R. (2002). Aristotle.

  • Lacey, N (1994) State Punishment: Political Principles and Community Values (2nd ed.).

  • Lacey, N (2001) Responsibility and Modernity in Criminal Law, 9 Journal of Political Philosophy 249

  • Lacey, N (2008) Women, Crime and Character: From Moll Flanders to Tess of the d’Urbervilles

  • Lacey, N (2010) Psychologising Jekyll, Demonising Hyde: The Strange Case of Criminal Responsibility; 4 Criminal Law and Philosophy 110

  • Lacey, N (2013) The Resurgence of Character: Responsibility in the Context of Criminalization; In R.A. Duff & S. Green (Eds.) Philosophical Foundations of Criminal Law.

  • Lee, Y (2009) Recidivism as Omission: A Relational Account, 87 Tex. L. Rev. 571 (2009).

  • Moore, M. S. (1990) Choice, Character, and Excuse, 7 Soc. Phil. & Pol’y. 29

  • Moore, M. S. (1998) Placing Blame

  • Morse, S. J. (1996) Blame and Danger: An Essay on Preventive Detention, 76 B.U. L. Rev. 113

  • Murphy, J. G. (1987) Does Kant Have a Theory of Punishment?, 87 Colum. L. Rev. 509

  • Pettit, P. (1989) The Freedom of the City: A Republican Ideal, in The Good Polity, Alan Hamlin and Philip Pettit (eds.),

  • Pettit, P. (1999) Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government

  • Postema, G. J. (2010), Rights, Equality, and Justice: A Conference Inspired by the Moral and Legal Theory of David Lyons: Law’s Ethos: Reflections on the Public Practice of Illegality, 90 B.U.L. Rev. 1847, 1856.

  • Rawls, J. (1999), Two Concepts of Rules, 64 Philosophical Rev. 3, 3-18 (1955), reprinted in JOHN RAWLS, Two Concepts of Rules, in John Rawls: Collected Papers 20, 20–33.

  • Raz, J (1986), The Morality of Freedom.

  • Ripstein, A. (2009), Force and Freedom: Kant’s Legal and Political Philosophy

  • Roberts, J. V. (1997) The Role of Criminal Record in the Sentencing Process, 22 Crime & Just. 303

  • Roberts, J. V. (2008) Punishing Persistent Offenders: Exploring Community and Offender Perspectives

  • Robinson, P. H. (2001) Punishing Dangerousness: Cloaking Preventive Detention as Criminal Justice, 114 Harv. L. Rev. 1429

  • Smart, J.J.C. (1973) An Outline of a System of Utilitarian Ethics, in Utilitarianism: For and Against J.J.C Smart & Bernard Williams (eds.) 1, 7

  • Skinner, Q. (1978) The Foundations of Modern Political Thought Vol. 1

  • Skinner, Q. (1984) The Idea of Negative Liberty: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives in Philosophy in History R. Rorty, J.B. Schneewind and Q. Skinner (eds.)

  • Solum, L.B., (2006) Natural Justice, 51 Am. J. Juris. 65solum

  • Tadros, V. (2005) Criminal Responsibility

  • Vlastos, G. (1953), Isonomia; 74 Amer. J. of Phil. 337)

  • Von Hirsch, A (1986) Past or Future Crimes

  • Yankah, Ekow N. (2004) Good Guys and Bad Guys: Punishing Character, Equality and the Irrelevance of Moral Character to Criminal Punishment. 25 Cardozo L. Rev. 1019

  • Yankah, Ekow N. (2009) Virtue’s Domain, 2009 U. ll. L. Rev. 1167

  • Yankah, Ekow N. (2012) Legal Vices and Civic Virtue. 7 Criminal Law and Philosophy.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ekow N. Yankah.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Yankah, E.N. Republican Responsibility in Criminal Law. Criminal Law, Philosophy 9, 457–475 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-013-9283-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-013-9283-0

Keywords

Navigation