Skip to main content
Log in

More Constraints, More Freedom: Revisit Semiotic Scaffolding, Semiotic Freedom, and Semiotic Emergence

  • Research
  • Published:
Biosemiotics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract  

How semiotic freedom emerges in the evolution and development of organisms through semiotic scaffolding is a core problem for biosemiotics. There is a paradox in explaining this semiotic emergence: reduction in (semiotic) freedom leads to the creation of new semiotic freedom. Semiotic emergence is a species of dynamic emergence. Accordingly, the paradox of semiotic emergence is a species of the paradox of dynamic emergence. The latter paradox claims that reducing lower-level freedom generates new freedom at a higher level. The solution to the paradox lies in clarifying the ambiguity in the term freedom. The conceptual inconsistency in the paradox comes from confusing two types of freedom. One type of freedom means the possibility a system could have, while the other refers to the capacity of a system to access a specific (range of) state(s). There is an inverse relation between the two types of freedom. With the clarification, the conceptual inconsistency is explained away. This understanding of semiotic emergence may help us further understand core ideas in biosemiotics and provide a conceptual foundation for empirical studies of biosemiotics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A reviewer helps me reformulate the description of E. Coli’s modes of action. Thanks very much for it.

  2. Higuera (2016) provides an excellent philosophical analysis of the emergence of semiosis within the metaphysical framework of emergence. I agree with his arguments but still prefer the concept of dynamic emergence because semiotic emergence is naturalistically explainable while irreducible.

  3. A reviewer helps me rephrase the description. I appreciate it very much.

  4. It may be misleading to use the concept of freedom in the context of inanimate dynamics. The concept is usually used in the living context. It refers to living organisms’ ability to act at the macro-scale. The notions of freedom for morphodynamics and teleodynamics (living dynamics) differ. For morphodynamics, a dynamic system can access macro scale presence, which was previously almost impossible. What is novel for organisms is their semiotic freedoms. Nevertheless, they share the common ground that the probabilities of accessing previously highly improbable states are highly enhanced. So, I still employ the concept and name it freedom2 to highlight the common ground. Thanks for the reviewer and several audiences reminding me of this.

References    

  • Bedau, M. (1997). Weak emergence. Philosophical Perspectives, 11, 375–399.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. (2002). Downward causation and the autonomy of weak emergence. Principia, 6(1), 5–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, R., Silberstein, M., & Pexton, M. (2021). Emergence in Context. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruni, L. E. (2008). Semiotic freedom: Emergence and teleology in biological and cognitive interfaces. The American Journal of Semiotics, 24(1/3), 57–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cuonzo, M. (2014). Paradox. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (1997). The symbolic species: Co-evolution of language and the brain. W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (2003). The hierarchical logic of emergence: Untangling the interdependence of evolution and self-organization. In B. Weber & D. Depew (Eds.), Evolution and Learning: The Baldwin effect reconsidered (pp. 273–308). The MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (2006). Reciprocal linkage between Self-organizing processes is sufficient for self-reproduction and evolvability. Biological Theory, 1(2), 136–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (2008). Emergence: The hole at the wheel’s hub. In P. Clayton & P. Davies (Eds.), The re-emergence of emergence: The emergentist hypothesis from science to religion (pp. 110–150). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (2012). Incomplete nature: How mind emerged from matter. W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (2015). Steps to a science of biosemiotics. Green Letters: Studies in Ecocriticism, 19(3), 293–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (2020). Teleodynamics: specifying the principles of intrinsically end-directed processes. In Proceedings of the IAISAE 2020, International Conference on Thermodynamics 2.0 (pp. 1–7). Worcester.

  • Deacon, T. (2021). How molecules become signs. Biosemiotics, 14, 537–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (2023). A thermodynamic basis for teleological causality. Philosophical Transactions A, 381, 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Depew, D. J., & Weber, B. H. (1995). Darwinism evolving: System dynamics and the genealogy of natural selection. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Favareau, D. (2015). Symbols are grounded not in things, but in scaffolded relations and their semiotic constraints. Biosemiotics, 8, 235–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, W. (2001). Cybernetic cells. Scientific American, 285, 52–57.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Gillet, C. (2016). Reduction and Emergence in Science and Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2016). Individuality, subjectivity, and minimal cognition. Biology & Philosophy, 31, 775–796.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Higuera, C. J. R. (2016). Just how emergent is the emergence of semiosis. Biosemiotics, 9, 155–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmeyer, J. (1996). Signs of meaning in the universe. Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmeyer, J. (2007). Semiotic Scaffolding of Living Systems. In M. Barbieri (Ed.), Introduction to Biosemiotics. The New Biological Synthesis (pp. 149–166). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmeyer, J. (2008). Biosemiotics: An examination into the signs of life and the life of signs. Scranton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmeyer, J. (2010). Semiotic freedom: An emerging force. In P. Davies & N. H. Gregersen (Eds.), Information and the nature of reality: From physics to metaphysics (pp. 185–204). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmeyer, J. (2014). The smiome: From genetic to semiotic scaffolding. Semiotica, 198, 11–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmeyer, J. (2015). Semiotic scaffolding of multicellularity. Biosemiotics, 8, 159–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmeyer, J., & Emmeche, C. (1991). Code-duality and the semiotics of nature. In M. Anderson & F. Merrell (Eds.), On Semiotic Modeling (pp. 117–166). De Gruyter Mouton.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Juarrero, A. (1998). Causality as constraint. In G. Vijver, S. Salthe, & M. Deplos (Eds.), Evolutionary systems: Biological and Epistemological Perspectives on Selection and Self-Organization (pp. 233–242). Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. (1993). The origin of order: Self-organization and selection in evolution. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S., Logan, R. K., Goebel, R., Hobill, D., & Shmulevich, I. (2008). Propagating organization: An enquiry. Biology & Philosophy, 23, 27–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1999). Making sense of emergence. Philosophical Studies, 95, 3–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kull, K. (2018). Choosing and learning: Semiosis means choice. Sign Systems Studies, 46(4), 452–466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kull, K., Emmeche, C., & Hoffmeyer, J. (2011). Why biosemiotics? An introduction to our view on the biology of life itself. In C, Emmeche & K. Kull (Eds). Towards a semiotic biology: life is the action of sign (pp. 1–21). London: Imperial College Press.

  • O’Connor, T. (2021). Emergent Properties. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/properties-emergent/. Accessed 10 Sept 2023.

  • Pattee, H. H. (1973). The Physical Basis and Origin of Hierarchical Control. In H. H. Pattee (Ed.), Hierarchy Theory: The Challenge of Complex Systems (pp. 71–108). Braziller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rueger, A. (2000). Physical emergence, diachronic and synchronic. Synthese, 124(3), 297–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salthe, S. (1985). Evolving hierarchical systems. Columbia University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sebeok, T. A. (1988). Communication, language and speech: Evolutionary considerations. In: Herzfeld, Michal (Eds). I Think I Am a Verb. Topics in Contemporary Semiotics. Boston, MA: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4899-3490-1_2

  • Sharov, A. (2014). Evolutionary constraints or opportunities? Bio Systems, 123, 9–18.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sharov, A., & Tønnessen, M. (2021). Semiotic Agency: Science Beyond Mechanism. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2007). Physical Realization. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ulanowicz, R. (1994). The propensities of evolving systems. In Khalil, E. L., & Boulding, K. E. (Eds), Social and natural systems (pp. 217–233). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • van Duijn, M., Keijzer, F., & Franken, D. (2006). Principles of minimal cognition: Casting cognition as sensorimotor coordination. Adaptive Behavior, 14(2), 157–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Uexküll, J. (1940). The theory of meaning. In D. Favareau (Ed.), Essential Readings in Biosemiotics: Anthology and commentary (pp. 90–114). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2010). Non-reductive physicalism and degrees of Freedom. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61, 279–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2015). Metaphysical Emergence: Weak and Strong. In Tomasz Bigaj & Christian Wüthrich (Eds.), Metaphysics in Contemporary Physics (pp. 251–306). Brill Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2021). Metaphysical Emergence. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Winning, J., & Bechtel, W. (2019). Being emergence VS pattern emergence. In S. C. Gibb, R. F. Hendry, & T. Lancaster (Eds.), Routledge Handbook of Emergence (pp. 134–144). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Liqian Zhou wrote 100% of the paper.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Liqian Zhou.

Ethics declarations

Competing interests

The authors declare no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Zhou, L. More Constraints, More Freedom: Revisit Semiotic Scaffolding, Semiotic Freedom, and Semiotic Emergence. Biosemiotics 16, 395–413 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-023-09548-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-023-09548-5

Keywords

Navigation