Skip to main content
Log in

A Basic Nietzschean Model in Lieu of the Causal Maxim

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Causal knowledge unquestionably provides useful means to describe, explain and predict both natural and daily phenomena. This article addresses whether causality as such may not be ontologically primary and looks for an alternative fundamental mechanism encapsulating the information load of the causal framework. A probabilistic process view of reality asserting the struggle of natural forces is considered along with lines quoted from Nietzsche’s posthumously published notebooks and published work. Examples from scientific discoveries, in particular neurosciences, echoing his ontology are provided. Furthermore, I propose a basic number game algorithm to illustrate and model the struggle of forces leading to causal inferences for an external observer. Nietzschean dynamic ontology involving the ceaseless struggle of will-to-power units accords with the emergentist approach to causation, which has been principally employed by the scientists working under the fields of thermodynamics, quantum mechanics and complex dynamical systems.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The majority of quotations from Nietzsche in this text are from Nietzsche (2017), a recent translation of selections from his notebooks in the 1880s. I will denote WTP and the corresponding passage number while referring to them.

  2. Despite Nietzsche’s own disclaimer, I will use “will-to-power” and “force” interchangeably. Aside from Nietzsche’s own words, I will only use the term “force-centers” to signify the units of will-to-power throughout this text for the sake of consistency. Force in plural form will indicate force-centers and their assemblages in the text.

  3. This translation was more sound; this passage was taken for that reason from Nietzsche (2003/2006) corresponding to Notebook 38[12], 1885.

  4. I have preferred to use the translation of this passage given by Rayman (2016), since it is more literal.

  5. See, for example, the essay “Eat Rat, Make New Body: Easy Stuff for Pythons”, published in The New York Times, 22/05/2020 (https://www.nytimes.com/2020/05/12/science/pythons-metabolism-animals-digestion.html).

  6. One of the chief contemporary neuroscientists, György Buzsáki explains how minor and local perturbations may induce totally unexpected outputs in the brain indicating its inherent irregular and acausal nature (Buzsáki, 2019). He lists several neuroscientific facts in this regard, one of which is on parkinsonian motor symptoms: “Decreased dopamine is a necessary but not always sufficient condition for the symptoms to occur, and similar symptoms may also occur in the absence of dopamine dysfunction.” According to Buzsáki, since brains are non-linear complex self-organizing dynamical systems, “events are not caused but emerge from the interaction of multiple elements.”

  7. The most natural symmetric probability density function to choose is Gaussian when one considers the “central limit theorem” of probability theory in order to represent a normal but diverse background of many forces. One is more liberal to choose D; an exemplary intuitive choice could be \(D=c\frac{x-y}{x+y}\), where c is any appropriate constant value.

  8. A plain software code for the game was written and is available upon request from me.

References

  • Aydin, C. (2007). Nietzsche on reality as will to power: Toward an "organization—struggle" model. Journal of Nietzsche Studies, 25–48.

  • Bargmann, C. I., & Marder, E. (2013). From the connectome to brain function. Nature Methods, 10(6), 483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berninger, B. (2012). Causality and the brain. RCC Perspectives, 6, 23–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borgstein, J., & Grootendorst, C. (2002). Half a brain. The Lancet, 359(9305), 473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boschetti, F. (2012). Causality, emergence, computation and unreasonable expectations. Synthese, 185(2), 187–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bukharin, N. (2005). Philosophical arabesques. Translated by Renfrey Clarke. Monthly Review Press.

  • Burnet, J. (1920). Greek philosophy: Thales to Plato (Vol. 3), Third Edition. Macmillan.

  • Buzsáki, G. (2019). The brain from inside out. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K. J. (1994). Functional and effective connectivity in neuroimaging: A synthesis. Human Brain Mapping, 2(1-2), 56–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K. J. (2010). The free-energy principle: A unified brain theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11(2), 127–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K. J. (2011). Functional and effective connectivity: A review. Brain Connectivity, 1(1), 13–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, C. J., Fliegen, S., Groiss, S. J., Wojtecki, L., & Schnitzler, A. (2019). An update on best practice of deep brain stimulation in Parkinson’s disease. Therapeutic Advances in Neurological Disorders, 12, 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D. M. (1998). Causal asymmetries. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heisenberg, W. (1930). The physical principles of the quantum theory. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock C. Probabilistic causation. (2018). In: E. N. Zalta, editor. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Fall 2018 edition. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/causality-probabilistic/.

  • Hoffman, D. (2019). The case against reality: Why evolution hid the truth from our eyes. Allen Lane.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1748/2011). An enquiry concerning human understanding, The Essential Philosophical Works. Wordsworth Editions Limited.

  • Jeans, J. (1942). Physics and philosophy. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kouloumentas, S. (2003). Heraclitus Pesseuon: Fragment 52. Philosophical inquiry, 25(3/4), 241–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lachaux, J. P., Rodriguez, E., Martinerie, J., & Varela, F. J. (1999). Measuring phase synchrony in brain signals. Human Brain Mapping, 8(4), 194–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, F. A., (1881). History of materialism and criticism of its present importance, Translated by Thomas, : Houghton, Osgood, & Company.

  • Mannino, M., & Bressler, S. L. (2015). Foundational perspectives on causality in large-scale brain networks. Physics of Life Reviews, 15, 107–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McWhirter, T. (1999). Nietzsche’s physics. International Studies in Philosophy, 31(3), 5–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., Bich, L., & Moreno, A. (2013). Emergence, closure and inter-level causation in biological systems. Erkenntnis, 78(2), 153–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science. Harcourt.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nathan, M. J. (2020). Causation vs. Causal explanation: Which is more fundamental? Foundations of Science. 10.1007/s10699-020-09672-2.

  • Neves, J. C. (2019). Nietzsche for Physicists. Philosophia Scientiæ, 23(1), 185-201

  • Nietzsche, F. (1954/1988). The portable Nietzsche. Translated by W. Kaufmann. Penguin Books.

  • Nietzsche, F. (1962/1998). Philosophy in the tragic age of the Greeks. Translated by M. Cowan. Regnery Publishing, Inc.

  • Nietzsche, F. (1968/2009). Basic writings of Nietzsche. . Random House Digital, Inc.

  • Nietzsche, F. (1974). The gay science. . Vintage Books.

  • Nietzsche, F. (2003/2006). Writings from the late notebooks. . Sturge, Cambridge University Press, Third Edition.

  • Nietzsche, F. (2017). The will to power. Translated by K. Hill and M. A. Scarpitti, Penguin Classics.

  • Noordhof, P. (2010). Emergent causation and property causation. Emergence in mind, 69–99.

  • Oreshkov, O., Costa, F., & Brukner, Č. (2012). Quantum correlations with no causal order. Nature Communications, 3(1), 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pallen, M. J. (2011). Time to recognise that mitochondria are bacteria? Trends in Microbiology, 19(2), 58–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prosser, S. (2012). Emergent causation. Philosophical Studies, 159(1), 21–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rayman, J. (2014). Nietzsche on causation. The Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 28(3), 327–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1956). The direction of time. University of California Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, J. (1996). Nietzsche’s system. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1913). On the notion of cause. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 13, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, A. (1883/2015). The world as will and representation, Translated by R. B. Haldane and J. Kemp, CreateSpace Independent Publishing Platform, Seventh Edition.

  • Small, R. (1986). Boscovich contra Nietzsche. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 46(3), 419–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stack, G. J. (1981). Nietzsche and Boscovich's natural philosophy. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 62(1), 69–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steinhart, E. (1999). Nietzsche’s philosophy of mathematics. International Studies in Philosophy, 31(3), 19–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tamm, M. (2021). Is causality a necessary tool for understanding our universe, or is it a part of the problem? Entropy, 23(7), 886.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Welshon, R. (2014). Nietzsche's dynamic metapsychology: This uncanny animal. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • West, S. A., Fisher, R. M., Gardner, A., & Kiers, E. T. (2015). Major evolutionary transitions in individuality. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 112(33), 10112–10119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zwart, H. (2019). Fabricated truths and the pathos of proximity: What would be a Nietzschean philosophy of contemporary technoscience? Foundations of Science, 24(3), 457–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Timothy West, Igor Mapelli and M. Hilmi Demir for their comments on the first draft of the article. I am thankful to Gökçe Gökalp, Pınar Varol and Leslie Demir for proofreading the article.

Data availability

Not applicable.

Code availability

It is available upon reasonable request.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tolga Esat Özkurt.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The author states that there is no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Özkurt, T.E. A Basic Nietzschean Model in Lieu of the Causal Maxim. Philosophia 50, 1343–1363 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00430-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00430-7

Keywords

Navigation