Skip to main content
Log in

Ignorance, norms and instrumental pluralism: Hayekian institutional epistemology

  • Knowing the Unknown
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Building on Friedrich A. Hayek’s work in social philosophy, the paper gives an account of the central role of ignorance in institutional epistemology. The first part of the paper argues that if individuals involved in the search for knowledge are constitutionally ignorant and guided by norms, as Hayek saw them, they are more likely to attain knowledge if they follow different norms, including those that are redundant. The second part of the paper argues that the market as an institutional arrangement, preferred by Hayek for its epistemic features, may lead to an epistemically detrimental reduction of agents following redundant norms.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Boettke specifically recognizes Hayek’s project as epistemological institutionalism.

  2. See Sellars 1963 for a more detailed understanding of the described pragmatist dynamics, and Aligica 2014, p. 78 for an account of the search for knowledge as the pursuit of adaptive isomorphism between the cognized and operative environment of the agent.

  3. Even if they were fully benevolent and outstandingly wise, the central board of planners (experts or elected officials), to whom all epistemic labour is delegated within a centralized system, would still firstly foreclose the ability of the population to make use of dispersed information (and thus epistemically unjustifiably reduce the inferential and conceptual capacity of the social epistemic system in the search for knowledge), and secondly are still ignorant (only supposedly relatively less so according to particular standards) and still themselves may only bet. With regards to experts’ ignorance, see Gaus 2008 and, on the particular issues with the foundational problem for development of expertise with regards to the wider concerns of policy and system design, see Rittel and Webber 1973.

  4. An additional clarification must be made. Agents are of course capable of various epistemic activities, have various epistemic resources at their disposal and may produce significant epistemic outcomes when lacking these conditions. However, the system which fails to constrain social epistemic exclusion is, from the standpoint of institutional epistemology, a system (in which agents are) less likely to attain knowledge. The inconsistent and defective provision of sustenance and access to epistemic resources as well as the diminished possibility of Epistemic Contribution put agents at a significant disadvantage in their search for knowledge. Their counterparts which have these conditions satisfied are more likely (but given their suboptimality, in no way guaranteed) to attain knowledge.

  5. There could be further arguments against social epistemic exclusion upon bad betting. For instance, it could be argued that the exclusion cannot ever be fully epistemologically justified due to the judging of the epistemic status of the bet itself being a bet. The presently recognized bad bets may be falsely recognized as such (Berg 2003, p. 414-415). Moreover, given all agents are epistemically suboptimal, no agent can with full justification predict any agent’s future bets from their history of betting (Sunstein 2006, p. 87).

References

  • Aligica, P. D. (2014). Institutional diversity and political economy: The Ostroms and beyond. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aligica, P. D., Boettke, P. J., & Tarko, V. (2019). Public governance and the classical-liberal perspective. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aligica, P. D., & Tarko, V. (2013). Co-production, polycentricity, and value heterogeneity: The Ostroms’ public choice institutionalism revisited. American Political Science Review, 107(4), 726–741.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E. (2006). The epistemology of democracy. Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology, 3(1-2), 8–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod, R. (1986). An evolutionary approach to norms. The American Political Science Review, 80(4), 1095–1111.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berg, N. (2003). Normative behavioral economics. Journal of Socio-Economics, 32, 411–427.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bicchieri, C. (2006). The grammar of society: The nature and dynamics of social norms. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bicchieri, C. (2017). Norms in the wild: How to diagnose, measure, and change social norms. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boettke, P. (2018). F. A. Hayek: Economics, political economy and social philosophy. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boettke, P. J., Caceres, W. Z., & Martin, A. G. (2013). Error is obvious, coordination is the puzzle. In R. Frantz & R. Leeson (Eds.), Hayek and behavioral economics (pp. 90–110). New York: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (2001). Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing and discursive commitment. Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caldwell, B., & Reiss, J. (2006). Hayek, logic, and the naturalistic fallacy. Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 28(3), 359–370.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Agostino, F. (2009). From organization to division of cognitive labor. Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 8(1), 101–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Esposto, A. (2014). Path dependence, lock-in, and social norms. International Journal of Economic Issues, 7(1), 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleetwood, S. (1995). Hayek’s political economy: The socio-economics of order. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, M. (2015). Epistemic contribution as a central human capability. In G. Hull (Ed.), The equal society (pp. 73–91). London: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2008). Is the public incompetent? Compared to whom? About what? Critical Review, 20, 291–311.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2011). The order of public reason: A theory of freedom and morality in a diverse and bounded world. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2013). The evolution, evaluation and reform of social morality: A Hayekean analysis. In D. Levy & S. Peart (Eds.), Hayek and the modern economy (pp. 59–88). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2018). Political philosophy as the study of complex normative systems. Cosmos + Taxis, 5(2), 62–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guala, F., & Hindriks, F. (2015). A unified social ontology. The Philosophical Quarterly, 65(259), 177–201.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1945). The use of knowledge in society. The American Economic Review, 35(4), 519–530.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1960). The constitution of liberty (Definitive ed.). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1978a). Coping With Ignorance. Imprimis, 7(7), 1–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1978b). New studies in philosophy, politics, economics and history of ideas. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1982). Law, legislation and liberty: A new statement of the liberal principles of justice and political economy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (2014). The market and other orders. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heinrich, J. (2009). Why societies vary in their rates of innovation: The evolution of innovation-enhancing institutions. In S. Shennan & M. J. O’Brien (Eds.), Innovation in Cultural Systems: Contributions from Evolutionary Anthropology, Altenberg Workshops in Theoretical Biology. Altenberg: Konrad Lorenz Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, G. (1991). Hayek’s theory of cultural evolution: An evaluation in light of Vanberg’s critique. Economics and Philosophy, 7, 67–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, G. (2006). What are institutions? Journal of Economic Issues, 40(1), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, P. (2006). Liberalism and epistemic diversity: Mill’s sceptical legacy. Episteme, 3(3), 248–263.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kingston, C., & Caballero, G. (2009). Comparing theories of institutional change. Journal of Institutional Economics, 5(2), 151–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirzner, I. (1997). Entrepreneurial discovery and the competitive market process: An Austrian approach. Journal of Economic Literature, 35(1), 60–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1990). The division of cognitive labour. The Journal of Philosophy, 87(1), 5–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krstić, M. (2012). The role of rules in the evolution of the market system: Hayek’s concept of evolutionary epistemology. Economic Annals, 57(194), 123–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landemore, H. (2012). Why the many are smarter than the few and why it matters. Journal of Public Deliberation, 8(1), 7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayo-Wilson, C., Zollman, K., & Danks, D. (2011). The independence thesis: When individual and social epistemology diverge. Philosophy of Science, 78(4), 653–677.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1977). On liberty. In J. M. Robson (Ed.), The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Volume XVIII—Essays on Politics and Society Part I (On Liberty) (pp. 213–311). Toronto: Toronto University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muldoon, R., & Weisberg, M. (2011). Robustness and idealization in models of cognitive labor. Synthese, 183(2), 161–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • North, D. (1990). Institutions, institutional change, and economic performance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • North, D., & Denzau, A. (1994). Shared mental models: Ideologies and institutions. Kyklos, 47(1), 3–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Novak, M. (2018). Inequality: An entangled political economy perspective. Cham: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Driscoll, G. P., Jr., & Rizzo, M. J. (1985). The economics of time and ignorance. New York: Basil Blackwell Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E. (2000). Collective action and the evolution of social norms. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 14(3), 137–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E. (2005). Understanding institutional diversity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E. (2010). Beyond markets and states: Polycentric governance of complex economic systems. The American Economic Review, 100(3), 641–672.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E., & Hess, C. (2007). A framework for analyzing the knowledge commons. In E. Ostrom & C. Hess (Eds.), Understanding knowledge as a commons (pp. 41–83). Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Page, S. (2008). The difference: How the power of diversity creates better groups, schools, firms, and societies. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E. (2008). Situated normativity: The normative aspect of embodied cognition in unreflective action. Mind, 117(468), 973–1001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rittel, H., & Webber, M. (1973). Dilemmas in a general theory of planning. Policy Sciences, 4, 155–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, A., Prasnikar, V., Okuno-Fujiwara, M., Zamir, S., & Zamir, S. (1991). Bargaining and market behavior in Jerusalem, Ljubljana, Pittsburgh and Tokyo: An experimental study. The American Economic Review, 81(5), 1068–1095.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothstein, B. (2011). The quality of government: Corruption, social trust, and inequality in international perspective. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1963). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In W. Sellars (Ed.), Science, perception and reality (pp. 127–197). Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. (1996). Social norms and social roles. Columbia Law Review, 96(4), 903–968.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. (2006). Infotopia: How many minds produce knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarko, V. (2015). The role of ideas in political economy. Review of Austrian Economics, 28, 17–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V. (2006). Rationality, rule-following and emotions: on the economics of moral preferences. In Papers on economics and evolution, 0621. Jena: Max Planck Institute of Economics.

  • Wallis, J. J. (2011). Institutions, organizations, impersonality, and interests: The dynamics of institutions. Journal of Economic Behaviour and Organization, 79(1–2), 48–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2010). New approaches to the division of cognitive labor. In P. D. Magnus, J. Busch, & J. Busch (Eds.), New waves in philosophy of science (pp. 250–269). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M., & Muldoon, R. (2009). Epistemic landscapes and the division of cognitive labour. Philosophy of Science, 76(2), 225–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zollman, K. (2010). The epistemic benefit of transient diversity. Erkenntnis, 72(1), 17–35.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marko-Luka Zubčić.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Zubčić, ML. Ignorance, norms and instrumental pluralism: Hayekian institutional epistemology. Synthese 198, 5529–5545 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02420-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02420-5

Keywords

Navigation