Skip to main content
Log in

Moral rights without balancing

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

How should we think about apparent conflicts of moral rights? I defend a non-balancing and holistic specification model: non-balancing because moral rights have absolute deontic stringency regardless of any balance of independent values; holistic because the content of moral rights is limited only by that of other moral rights. Holistic Specification, as I call the model, offers a principled, non-consequentialist explanation of exceptions to moral rights. Moreover, Holistic Specification explains why moral rights matter to practical thought while rendering remedial duties less mysterious.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Many philosophers operate with the notion of a conflict of rights without carefully defining it. A classic definition, when offered, is that articulated by Jeremy Waldron: a conflict of rights tracks the incompatibility of the generated duties (Waldron, 1989, 505). See also Preda (2015, 679). But as Rainbolt argues, for instance, some conflicts are better understood in terms of the incompatibility of a duty with a permission—rather than with other duties (2006, 158). My working definition is deliberately meant to be more capacious.

  2. For a similar setup of a conflict case, see Shafer-Landau (1995).

  3. For current purposes, I shall treat the terms ‘duty’ and ‘obligation’ as synonymous.

  4. For a classic formulation of the view, see Thomson (1986). For more recent defenses, see Montague (1988, 2001) and Frederick (2014).

  5. In the literature, the term ‘prima facie’ is often taken to be equivalent to ‘pro tanto’, perhaps in deference to W. D. Ross’s influential use of this term (1930, 1–20). But this is ambiguous. As some have noticed, there are two fundamental senses of ‘prima facie’ in Ross’s use: one is epistemic (‘x appears obligatory but isn’t’), the other is metaphysical (‘x has a certain moral force that may be cancelled out by the force of competing reasons’). As far as I can tell, this distinction makes no difference for the issues I shall consider here. For discussion of this aspect of reasons, see Brink (1994, 218) and Reisner (2013). For discussion of Ross’s view, see Hurka (2014, 70–78).

  6. For a classic formulation of the view, see also Thomson (1986), who first labels as “Specification” the view under consideration. For defenses, see Donagan (1977), Steiner (1994), Shafer-Landau (1995), Wellman (1995), and Oberdiek (2008).

  7. “This rights citation is not explanatory in the more robust sense that Thomson desires, however, since the right merely marks, rather than explains, the relevant moral reasons” (Wellman, 1995, 282).

  8. Finkelstein restates the problem forcefully: “the strategies available to her [to Specification] to eliminate conflicts all determine the existence of a right in terms of the relative strength of the underlying claims. And once the relative strengths of the underlying claims have been settled, there is no longer any need for the assignment of rights. For any question of permissibility can be answered by examining the claims on which the assignment of rights is based. For this reason, on the view that would eliminate conflicts, rights cannot themselves contribute to judgments of moral permissibility.” (2001, 288).

  9. Frederick (2014) argues that this problem is in fact fatal to Specification.

  10. It is not controversial that Prima Facie models make the Balancing assumption, since they build Balancing into the concept of a moral right. Here is some textual evidence that prominent defenders of Specification make this assumption as well. Wellman says that moral rights are “conclusions established by a balance of the relevant reasons.” (1995, 282) Shafer-Landau frankly acknowledges that “the problem of specifying the content of a right is the very same problem as that of balancing prima facie rights, or knowing when a right is permissibly infringed. In each case, conflicting moral considerations generate a moral conclusion either about what a full-fledged right contains, or about the circumstances under which a full-fledged right can be permissibly infringed.” (1995, 215). And Oberdiek says “Specificationism instead maintains that a right should be designated only after the final interaction of all of the reasons bearing upon the justifiability of a given action” (2008, 135).

  11. Griffin (2008) argues that the basis of human rights is a thin notion of the value of normative agency.

  12. The most articulate defense of the normative constraint theory I know is Rainbolt (2006). The classic debate in theories of rights is that between interest (Kramer, 2002; Raz, 1984) and choice (Steiner, 1994, 2013), along with a hybrid interest-choice theory (Sreenivasan, 2010) and Wenar's kind-desire theory (2013). A virtue of the normative constraint theory is that it is more basic than either the interest or choice theories, as Rainbolt himself argues, for it can be filled in by either theory. Here I adapt Rainbolt’s account to accommodate the relational normativity constitutive of rights (cf. Rainbolt, 2006, 28).

  13. On directed duties, see del Vecchio (1982), Weinrib (1995), Thompson (2004), Gilbert (2004, 2006, 35–40, and 2018), Cruft (2006), Darwall (2013), May (2015), and Wallace (2019). For a dissenting voice, questioning whether wrongs presuppose claim-rights, see Cornell (2015).

  14. The locus classicus of this point is Feinberg’s Nowheresville (1970).

  15. A fuller account would show how to construct moral normative powers, such as the power to promise or consent, out of this spare formulation. For our purposes, I believe the current formulation suffices.

  16. I think one of the few philosophers who focuses on the issue of atomism in moral philosophy and who attempts to formulate an alternative is Barbara Herman (2012, 2013). I see my work here as complementing Herman’s.

  17. Scanlon also marks the important distinction between balancing values and adjusting rights (2004). But this distinction is not embedded into a general theory of the connection between rights and obligation. Scanlon doesn’t contrast Specification to Prima Facie nor does he distinguish the crucial theses concerning stringency and content. Yet, I suspect that Scanlon’s view is sympathetic to the model I am articulating here.

  18. How exactly does Holistic Specification apply to apparent conflicts involving exclusively non-moral rights? I cannot fully address this question, but a very rough and preliminary answer is that Holistic Specification can be naturally extended to non-moral domains. An example of how to do so for rights under private law might be the “formalistic” theory defended by Ernest Weinrib (1995), according to which private legal rights get specified holistically. I’m grateful to an anonymous referee for raising this important question.

  19. There is a good question here about how Holistic Specification can handle cases where moral rights appear to conflict with consequentialist considerations (e.g., torture one to save five) and in particular with cases that appear to require a consequentialism of rights where we ought to minimize the violations of rights (e.g., switch a trolley to kill one instead of five). Since my aim here is not to argue against consequentialism, I cannot adequately address these questions here. My hunch is that Holistic Specification puts pressure towards anti-consequentialism, for instance, prohibiting the torture of one even if doing so might permit saving indefinite many more. Whether such a position is entailed by Holistic Specification and, if so, whether it’s plausible are good questions for further research on the model. I’m grateful to an anonymous referee for pressing me to address this important point.

  20. Thomson introduced the distinction between infringing and violating rights in order for her Prima Facie view to make conceptual space for the permissible infringement of moral rights. (Thomson, 1990, 122). For a Specificationist critique of this view, see Oberdiek (2004).

  21. For an insightful elaboration of this line of thought, see Shiffrin (2011).

  22. Jeremy Waldron expresses what I take to be a similar insight: “We ban their speeches, therefore, not because we think we can necessarily safeguard more rights by doing so, but because in their content and tendency the Nazis’s speeches are incompatible with the very idea of the right they are asserting. What looked like a brute confrontation between two rival interests, independently understood, turns out to be resolved by considering the internal relation that obtains between our understanding of the respective rights claims.” (1989, 518).

  23. Raz (1986, ch. 7).

  24. My thinking on this schema is inspired by the analysis of proportionality in law by Jacob Weinrib (2016, 215–256) and Arthur Ripstein (2017).

References

  • Brink, D. (1994). Moral conflict and its structure. Philosophical Review, 103(2), 215–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornell, N. (2015). Wrongs, rights, and third parties. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 43(2), 109–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cruft, R. (2006). Why aren’t duties rights? Philosophical Quarterly, 56, 175–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (2013). Bipolar obligation. In Morality, authority, and law: Essays in second-personal ethics I. Oxford University Press, pp. 20–39.

  • del Vecchio, G. (1982). Justice: An historical and philosophical essay (Guthrie L. Trans.) (New York: Philosophical Library).

  • Donagan, A. (1977). The theory of morality. The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frederick, D. (2014). Pro tanto versus absolute rights. Philosophical Forum, 45, 375–394.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1970) The Nature and value of rights. Journal of Value Inquiry, 4, 243–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (2004). Scanlon on promissory obligation: The problem of promisees’ rights. Journal of Philosophy, 101, 83–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (2006). A theory of political obligation: Membership, commitment, and the bonds of society. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (2018). Rights and demands: A foundational inquiry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Griffin, J. (2008). On human rights. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herman, B. (2012). Being helped and being grateful: imperfect duties, the ethics of possession, and the unity of morality. The Journal of Philosophy, 109(5), 391–411.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herman, B. (2013). Making Exceptions. In M. Ruffing, A. La Rocca, A. Ferrarin, & S. Bacin (Eds.), Kant Und Die Philosophie in Weltbürgerlicher Absicht: Akten des Xi: Kant-Kongresses 2010 (pp. 245–262). De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohfeld, W. (1913). Some fundamental legal conceptions as applied in legal reasoning. Yale Law Journal, 23, 16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, T. (2014). British Ethical theorists from sidgwick to ewing. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, F. (1992). Non-consequentialism, the person as an end-in-itself, and the significance of status. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 2(4), 354–389.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, F. (2001). Conflicts of rights: Typology methodology, and nonconsequentialism. Legal Theory, 7, 239–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, M. (2002). Rights without trimmings. In M. Kramer, N. Simmonds, & H. Steiner (Eds.), A debate over rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, S. C. (2015). Directed duties. Philosophy Compass, 10(8), 523–532.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, M., Simmonds, N., & Steiner, H. (2002). a debate over rights. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, P. (1988). When rights are permissibly infringed. Philosophical Studies: an International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, 53(3), 347–366.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, P. (2001). When rights conflict. Legal Theory, 7, 257–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (2002). Personal rights and public space. In Concealment and exposure: And other essays. Oxford University Press.

  • Oakes Finkelstein, C. (2001). Two men and a plank. Legal Theory, 7, 279–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oberdiek, J. (2004). Lost in moral space: On the infringing/violating distinction and its place in the theory of rights. Law and Philosophy, 23, 325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oberdiek, J. (2008). Specifying rights out of necessity. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 28(1), 127–146.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preda, A. (2015). Are there any conflicts of rights? Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 18, 677–690.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rainbolt, G. (2006). The concept of rights. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1985). Justice as fairness: Political, not metaphysical. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 14(3), 223–251.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1984). On the nature of rights. Mind, 93, 194–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1986). The morality of freedom. Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reisner, A. (2013). Prima facie and pro tanto oughts. In H. LaFollete (Ed.), The international encyclopedia of ethics. Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ripstein, A. (2017). Reclaiming proportionality. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 34(1), 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (1930). The right and the good. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (2004). Adjusting rights and balancing values. Fordham Law Review, 72(5), 1477–1486.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. (1995). Specifying absolute rights. Arizona Law Review, 37, 209–224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shiffrin, S. (2011). A thinker-based approach to freedom of speech. Constitutional Commentary, 27(2), 283–307.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sreenivasan, G. (2010). Duties and their direction. Ethics, 120, 465–494.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, H. (1994). An essay on rights. Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, H. (2013). Directed duties and inalienable rights. Ethics, 123(2), 230–244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M. (2004). What is it to wrong someone a puzzle about justice. In R. Jay Wallace, P. Pettit, S. Scheffler, & M. Smith (Eds.), Reason and value: Themes from the moral philosophy of Joseph Raz (pp. 333–384). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. (1986). Self-defense and rights. In Rights, restitution, and risk: Essays in moral theory. Harvard University Press

  • Thomson, J. (1990). The realm of rights. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (1989). Rights in conflict. Ethics, 99(3), 503–519.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, R. J. (2019). The moral nexus. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinrib, E. (1995). The idea of private law. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinrib, J. (2016). Dimensions of dignity. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, C. (1995). On conflicts between rights. Law and Philosophy, 14(3), 271–295.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wenar, L. (2013). The nature of claim-rights. Ethics, 123, 202–229.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I’m grateful to audiences at Monash University, University of Oslo, University of Stirling, and my students in the rights seminar at UAlbany for their feedback. I'm especially grateful for helpful comments on previous drafts from Linda Barclay, Sam Black, Rowan Cruft, Chris Essert, Suzy Killmister, Reidar Maliks, Øyvind Rabbås, Arthur Ripstein, Oliver Sensen, John Tasioulas, Owen Ware, Jacob Weinrib, and Moran Yahav.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ariel Zylberman.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Zylberman, A. Moral rights without balancing. Philos Stud 179, 549–569 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01670-9

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01670-9

Keywords

Navigation