Extrinsic Denomination and the Origins of Early Modern Metaphysics: The Scholastic Context of Descartes’s Regulae
In Nicolas Faucher & Magali Roques (eds.), The Ontology, Psychology and Axiology of Habits in Medieval Philosophy. Springer. pp. 385-401 (2018)
Abstract
An assessment of Descartes’s relation to his Aristotelian contemporaries in his Regulae ad directionem ingenii—and more specifically his relation to the theory of scientific habitus—has never been undertaken and is long overdue. Despite broad scholarly consensus that Descartes rejected the scholastic theory of scientific habitus in the Regulae, I will show that, in fact, he redefines a centuries-old scholastic debate about the unity of science, and that he does so by employing, not rejecting, the concept of scientific habitus. For Descartes, the sciences are collectively one in virtue of a habitus which inclines the intellect to regard all things, not as they are in reality, but rather as they are relative to the intellect alone. Descartes establishes the unity of science via what Suárez refers to as “extrinsic denomination” in Disputationes metaphysicae 44.11.64. This creates a serious problem. As he no doubt knew and as Suárez would have rightly pointed out, the extrinsic denominations that Descartes employs in the Regulae have no ontological basis in the things denominated. Descartes’s method creates, arguably for the first time, a chasm between how things can be known by the intellect and how they are in reality—i.e., between “epistemology” and “ontology”—that motivates him to pursue metaphysics after the Regulae.Author's Profile
My notes
Similar books and articles
Rule VIII of Descartes’ Regulae ad directionem ingenii.Patrick Brissey - 2014 - Journal of Early Modern Studies 3 (2):9-31.
The Method of the "Regulae" and its Imperfectly Understood Relationship to Cartesian Science.Glenn Nicholas Statile - 1998 - Dissertation, City University of New York
Descartes’s Translation Problem.Glenn Statile - 2005 - International Philosophical Quarterly 45 (2):187-202.
Regulae Ad Directionem Ingenii. Cogitationes Privatae: Regeln Zur Ausrichtung der Geisteskraft - Private Gedanken.René Descartes - 2011 - Felix Meiner Verlag.
The Form of Descartes’ Method of Doubt.Patrick Brissey - 2017 - Southwest Philosophy Review 33 (2):233-249.
De la figure à l'idée: note sur l'usage d' 'idea' dans les Regulae ad directionem ingenii.Lynda Gaudemard - 2008 - Etudes de Philosophie 1 (9-10):254-274.
Descartes and Method in 1637.Daniel Garber - 1988 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988:225-236.
Method, Practice, and the Unity of Scientia in Descartes’s Regulae.Tarek R. Dika - 2015 - Journal of Early Modern Studies 4 (2):93-110.
Descartes’s ens summe perfectum et infinitum and its Scholastic Background.Igor Agostini - 2018 - In Igor Agostini, Richard T. W. Arthur, Geoffrey Gorham, Paul Guyer, Mogens Lærke, Yitzhak Y. Melamed, Ohad Nachtomy, Sanja Särman, Anat Schechtman, Noa Shein & Reed Winegar (eds.), Infinity in Early Modern Philosophy. Springer Verlag. pp. 9-25.
Towards Descartes’ Scientific Method: a posteriori Evidence and the Rhetoric of Les Météores.Patrick Brissey - 2018 - In James Lancaster & Richard Raiswell (eds.), Evidence in the Age of the New Sciences. Springer. pp. pp. 77-99.
The Origins of Descartes' Concept of Mind in the Regulae ad directionem ingenii.Nathan D. Smith - 2010 - Dissertation, Boston College
Cartesian Metaphysics: The Scholastic Origins of Modern Philosophy.Jorge Secada - 2000 - Cambridge University Press.
Cartesian Metaphysics: The Scholastic Origins of Modern Philosophy.A. Pessin - 2002 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (209):635-637.
Analytics
Added to PP
2020-06-17
Downloads
6 (#1,105,256)
6 months
1 (#451,971)
2020-06-17
Downloads
6 (#1,105,256)
6 months
1 (#451,971)
Historical graph of downloads
Author's Profile
Citations of this work
Descartes’s Deduction of the Law of Refraction and the Shape of the Anaclastic Lens in Rule 8.Tarek R. Dika - 2022 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 12 (2):395-446.