Rationalizable behavior in the Hotelling–Downs model of spatial competition

Theory and Decision 95 (2):309-335 (2023)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

We consider two scenarios of the Hotelling–Downs model of spatial competition. This setting has typically been explored using pure Nash equilibrium, but this paper uses point rationalizability (Bernheim, Econometrica J Economet Soc 52(4):1007–1028, 1984) instead. Pure Nash equilibrium imposes a correct beliefs assumption, which may rule out perfectly reasonable choices in a game. Point rationalizability does not have this correct beliefs assumption, which makes this solution concept more natural and permissive. The first scenario is the original Hotelling–Downs model with an arbitrary number of agents. Eaton and Lipsey (Rev Econ Stud 42(1):27–49, 1975) used pure Nash equilibrium as their solution concept for this setting. They showed that with three agents, there does not exist a pure Nash equilibrium. We characterize the set of point rationalizable choices for any number of agents and show that as the number of agents increases, the set of point rationalizable choices increases as well. In the second scenario, agents have limited attraction intervals (Feldman et al. Variations on the Hotelling–Downs model. In: Thirtieth AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence, pp 496–501, 2016). We show that the set of point rationalizable choices does not depend on the number of agents, apart from this number being odd or even. Furthermore, the set of point rationalizable choices shrinks as the attraction interval increases.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,475

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Announcement.[author unknown] - 1999 - Theory and Decision 46 (1):106-106.
Annoucement.[author unknown] - 2004 - Theory and Decision 56 (3):iii-iii.
Foreword.[author unknown] - 2004 - Theory and Decision 56 (1):vii-x.
Announcement.[author unknown] - 1999 - Theory and Decision 46 (1):105-105.
Editorial.[author unknown] - 1998 - Theory and Decision 44 (1):V-VI.
List of Contributors.[author unknown] - 2004 - Theory and Decision 56 (4):407-408.
Contents Volume 55.[author unknown] - 2004 - Theory and Decision 55 (4):391-392.
Index of Authors.[author unknown] - 2003 - Theory and Decision 55 (4):392-392.
Index of Authors.[author unknown] - 2003 - Theory and Decision 54 (4):376-376.
Contents Volume 54.[author unknown] - 2003 - Theory and Decision 54 (4):375-376.
List of Contributors.[author unknown] - 2005 - Theory and Decision 58 (4):407-407.
List of contributors.[author unknown] - 2004 - Theory and Decision 57 (4):408-408.
Contents of Volume 58.[author unknown] - 2005 - Theory and Decision 58 (4):409-410.
Theory and Decision, Contents of Volume 57.[author unknown] - 2005 - Theory and Decision 57 (4):407-408.
Theory and Decision Contents Volume 56.[author unknown] - 2004 - Theory and Decision 56 (4):405-408.

Analytics

Added to PP
2023-01-17

Downloads
15 (#938,320)

6 months
10 (#260,500)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Rational beliefs in rationalizability.Xiao Luo - 2016 - Theory and Decision 81 (2):189-198.

Add more references