Does Kant's rejection of the right to resist make him a legal rigorist? Instantiation and interpretation in the rechtslehre

Kantian Review 13 (2):107-140 (2008)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

It is generally acknowledged that Kant's political philosophy stands on a par with the great works of the Western liberal tradition. It is also a matter of agreement that the rational principles on which it rests represent an adequate philosophical expression of the progressive agenda that was inaugurated by the Enlightenment and fulfilled, with varying degrees of success, by the French Revolution. Yet Kant's philosophical position is ambiguous when it comes to evaluating that momentous event in modern history. We know, from anecdotal evidence, some surviving letters, several cryptic references in his published works, as well as a number of posthumously published reflections, that Kant was enthusiastic about and strongly approved of the changes that were taking place in France at the time. He certainly condemned, in strong and unequivocal terms, the execution of Louis XVI. But this did not translate into a repudiation of his support for the revolution. And he seems to have found even in this case mitigating circumstances that explained the revolutionaries' decision to execute the monarch, thus in fact excusing their action. Moreover, he argued that all post-revolutionary governments ought to command the same kind of loyalty from their subjects as the ones they replaced, which appears to justify Kant's contention in the Idea for a Universal History that political violence can be a vehicle of progress. Furthermore, in the Contest of Faculties Kant went so far as to identify in the enthusiastic response of the ‘spectators’ to the French Revolution a clear sign of the moral disposition of humankind

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 93,779

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The Sublimity of Violence.Radu Neculau - 2008 - Symposium 12 (1):29-43.
The Sublimity of Violence.Radu Neculau - 2008 - Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy/Revue canadienne de philosophie continentale 12 (1):29-43.
Kant’s Political Theory: The Virtue of His Vices.Dick Howard - 1980 - Review of Metaphysics 34 (2):325 - 350.
Revolutionary epigones: Kant and his radical followers.Reidar Maliks - 2012 - History of Political Thought 33 (4):647-671.
Conversations with Kant: On the Right to Revolution.Milica Smajevic Roljic - 2023 - In Nenad Cekić (ed.), Virtues and vices – between ethics and epistemology. Belgrade: Faculty of Philosophy, University of Belgrade. pp. 191-202.
Kant and the French Revolution.Reidar Maliks & Trad Agustín José Menéndez Menéndez - 2023 - Las Torres de Lucca: Revista Internacional de Filosofía Política 12 (2):113-119.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
63 (#249,787)

6 months
6 (#702,272)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Radu Neculau
University of Windsor

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy.Hannah Arendt - 1982 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Ronald Beiner.
Theory and Practice.Jürgen Habermas & John Viertel - 1975 - Studies in Soviet Thought 15 (4):341-351.
Kant's political philosophy.Howard Williams - 1983 - New York: St. Martin's Press.
Kant’s Theory of Justice.Allen Duncan Rosen - 1993 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

View all 25 references / Add more references