Maimonidean Aspects in Spinoza’s Thought

Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 17 (1-2):153-174 (1994)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

A cursory review of studies of Spinoza’s thought discloses that diverse and often opposed religious, philosophical, historical, even literary traditions have claimed and disclaimed his debt to them as well as theirs to him. A Jewish, Christian, pantheist, and atheist Spinoza vies with a rationalist and a mystic, a realist and a nominalist, an analytic and a continental, an historicist and an a-historical one. And this list is far from exhaustive of the dazzling array of further, nuanced debates and interpretations within each tradition. The irony exhibited by the history of Spinoza scholarship is especially poignant insofar as the debates and controversies surrounding his thought are rather heated or affective, this in relation to a thinker who strove to control, circumscribe, and transform the passions by the intellect. Following Spinoza’s motto caute, I shall attempt to evade the fray by disclaiming the possibility of a definitive interpretation not only because it is premature, but also and especially because I believe that Spinoza’s writings deliberately resist direct appropriation and translation into philosophically “respectable” language. In addition, while it is possible to identify Spinoza’s very few, explicit successors, e.g., Schelling, Lessing, Hölderlin, Hegel, and Nietzsche, it is exceedingly difficult to limit the list of his predecessors for two main reasons: he is both reticent to name and misleading in naming his predecessors—the latter only in the sense that he is sooner ready to identify an adversarial position than to acknowledge debt to the same thinker in other respects; and Spinoza’s debt to his varied predecessors is neither consistent nor systematic, for his diverse discussions are informed by different considerations, positions, and thinkers, at times only in a negative way. In fact, one of the common problems characterizing contemporary Spinoza scholarship is the resolve to ignore or dismiss the significance of such “negative” influences. For these reasons alone, we should be wary of attempts to systematize Spinoza’s thought or to regard him as a system builder, despite such attempts by his late-eighteenth and nineteenth century disciples, especially Schelling and Hegel. But, in addition, in the Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione, Spinoza cautions the reader to refrain from judgments concerning the truth or falsity of philosophical discussions on the basis of some paradoxical statements

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,928

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The Maimonidean Controversy.Idit Dobbs-Weinstein - 1997 - In Daniel H. Frank & Oliver Leaman (eds.), History of Jewish Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 2--331.
A portrait of Spinoza as a maimonidean.Warren Harvey - 1981 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 19 (2):151-172.
The Garden of Eden.Heidi M. Ravven - 2001 - Philosophy and Theology 13 (1):3-51.
The Power of Prejudice and the Force of Law.Idit Dobbs-Weinstein - 2002 - Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 7 (1):51-70.
Spinoza’s Revelation: Religion, Democracy, and Reason.Nancy Levene - 2004 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
Spinoza and the Case for Philosophy by Elhanan Yakira.Karolina Hübner - 2016 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 54 (1):170-171.
Spinoza, the man and his thought.Edward Leroy Schaub (ed.) - 1933 - Chicago,: The Open court publishing company.

Analytics

Added to PP
2012-03-18

Downloads
44 (#361,366)

6 months
10 (#268,500)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Idit Dobbs-Weinstein
Vanderbilt University

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references