Does Science Progress Towards Ever Higher Solvability Through Feedbacks Between Insights and Routines?

Studia Semiotyczne 32 (2):153-185 (2018)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The affirmative answer to the title question is justified in two ways: logical and empirical. The logical justification is due to Gödel’s discovery that in any axiomatic formalized theory, having at least the expressive power of PA, at any stage of development there must appear unsolvable problems. However, some of them become solvable in a further development of the theory in question, owing to subsequent investigations. These lead to new concepts, expressed with additional axioms or rules. Owing to the so-amplified axiomatic basis, new routine procedures like algorithms, can be reached. Those, in turn, help to gain new insights which lead to still more powerful axioms, and consequently again to ampler algorithmic resources. Thus scientific progress proceeds to an ever higher scope of solvability. The existence of such feedback cycles –in a formal way rendered with Turing’s systems of logic based on ordinal – gets empirically supported by the history of mathematics and other exact sciences. An instructive instance of such a process is found in the history of the number zero. Without that insight due to some ancient Hindu mathematicians there could not arise such an axiomatic theory as PA. It defines the algorithms of arithmetical operations, which in turn help intuitions; those, inturn, give rise to algorithmic routines, not available in any of the previous phases of the process in question. While the logical substantiation of the point of this essay is a well-established result of logico-semantic inquiries, its empiricalclaim, based on historical evidences, remains open for discussion. Hence the author’s intention to address philosophers and historians of science, and to encourage their critical responses.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,435

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Is Mathematics Problem Solving or Theorem Proving?Carlo Cellucci - 2017 - Foundations of Science 22 (1):183-199.
Axiomatic Method in Contemporary Science and Technology.С.П Ковалев & А.В Родин - 2016 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 47 (1):153-169.
Hilbert, completeness and geometry.Giorgio Venturi - 2011 - Rivista Italiana di Filosofia Analitica Junior 2 (2):80-102.
Theories and Theories of Truth.Ryan Christensen - 2011 - Metaphysica 12 (1):31-43.
Axiomatic Method in Contemporary Science and Technology.Sergei Kovalyov & Andrei Rodin - 2016 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 47 (1):153-169.
The Notion of Explanation in Gödel’s Philosophy of Mathematics.Krzysztof Wójtowicz - 2019 - Studia Semiotyczne—English Supplement 30:85-106.
Randomness everywhere.C. S. Calude & G. J. Chaitin - 1999 - Nature 400:319-320.
Independence and justification in mathematics.Krzysztof Wójtowicz - 2006 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 91 (1):349-373.

Analytics

Added to PP
2020-06-10

Downloads
13 (#1,020,434)

6 months
6 (#510,035)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Witold Marciszewski
Warsaw University

Citations of this work

Filum Cogitationis. Remarks on Leibnizian Projects of a Universal Language.Halina Święczkowska - 2020 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 62 (1):113-136.
The Notion of Explanation in Gödel’s Philosophy of Mathematics.Krzysztof Wójtowicz - 2019 - Studia Semiotyczne—English Supplement 30:85-106.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Tractatus logico-philosophicus.Ludwig Wittgenstein - 1922 - Filosoficky Casopis 52:336-341.
The Language of Thought.J. A. Fodor - 1978 - Critica 10 (28):140-143.
The Logic of Scientific Discovery.K. Popper - 1959 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 10 (37):55-57.
On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem.Alan Turing - 1936 - Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society 42 (1):230-265.

View all 25 references / Add more references