Doing Without the Ideology of Art

New Literary History 42:71-79 (2011)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

My invited comment on Steven Connor’s essay, “Doing Without Art,” proposes that a fuller understanding of the implications of my notion of “making special”—referred to by Connor in his essay as somewhat relevant to his own position—would expand his view of the human art impulse and allay some of his disaffections. Rather than contributing to aesthetic theory, the ideology of art, my work proposes an ethology of art: it suggests why members of the human species, in all times and places, made and otherwise engaged with the arts. An ethology of art requires a new way of regarding its subject, not philosophically as an entity or essential quality but as a behavior, something that people everywhere “do.” What characterizes all instances of “doing with art,” from prehistory to the present, is making something special. A summary of the development and ramifications of the concept of “making special”—called “artifying” in my most recent work—answers Connor’s three questions and suggests that placing our modern ideology or ideologies of art in the wider and deeper context of artification enables an understanding of the arts as intrinsic and even necessary to human lives everywhere.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,846

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Evolutionary essentialism.Denis Walsh - 2006 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57 (2):425-448.
New Essentialism in Biology.Olivier Rieppel - 2010 - Philosophy of Science 77 (5):662-673.
Evolutionary Psychology: History and Current Status.Paul E. Griffiths - 2005 - In Sahotra Sarkar & Jessica Pfeifer (eds.), The Philosophy of Science: An Encyclopedia. New York: Routledge. pp. 263--268.
Essence and anti-essentialism about art.Lauren Tillinghast - 2004 - British Journal of Aesthetics 44 (2):167-183.
Shared aesthetic starting points?Roberta Dreon - 2015 - Aisthesis: Pratiche, Linguaggi E Saperi Dell’Estetico 8 (1):53-69.
Mental content and evolutionary explanation.Colin Allen - 1992 - Biology and Philosophy 7 (1):1-12.
Chimera, spandrel, or adaptation.Ellen Dissanayake - 1995 - Human Nature 6 (2):99-117.
Consciousness as an Adaptation. What animals feel and why.Pouwel Slurink - 2016 - In Andreas Blank (ed.), Animals: New Essays. Munich: Philosophia. pp. 303-332.
On aims and methods of cognitive ethology.Dale Jamieson & Marc Bekoff - 1992 - Philosophy of Science Association 1992:110-124.
Landscapes and Evolutionary Aesthetics.Roger Paden - 2016 - Environment, Space, Place 8 (1):33-55.
Essentialism and anti-essentialism in feminist philosophy.Alison Stone - 2004 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 1 (2):135-153.
Intentionality, social play, and definition.Colin Allen & Marc Bekoff - 1994 - Biology and Philosophy 9 (1):63-74.
“Aesthetic Primitives”: Fundamental Biological Elements of a Naturalistic Aesthetics.Ellen Dissanayake - 2015 - Aisthesis: Pratiche, Linguaggi E Saperi Dell’Estetico 8 (1):6-24.

Analytics

Added to PP
2016-07-04

Downloads
36 (#443,144)

6 months
3 (#973,855)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

Why Aesthetic Patterns Matter: Art and a “Qualitative” Social Theory.Eduardo Fuente - 2014 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 44 (2):168-185.
Why Aesthetic Patterns Matter: Art and a “Qualitative” Social Theory.Eduardo de la Fuente - 2014 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 44 (2):168-185.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references