Linked bibliography for the SEP article "Rigid Designators" by Joseph LaPorte
This is an automatically generated and experimental page
If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.
This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.
- Anscombe, G. E. M., & Geach, P. T., 1961, Three Philosophers, Ithaca: Cornell University Press. (Scholar)
- Bacon, Andrew, forthcoming, “Representing Counterparts,” Australasian Journal of Logic. (Scholar)
- Baker, Lynne R., 2000, Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View, New York: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Bealer, George, 2002, “Modal Epistemology and the Rationalist Renaissance,” in Tamar Gendler and John Hawthorne (eds.): Conceivability and Possibility, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 71–125. (Scholar)
- Besson, Corine, 2009, “Externalism, Internalism, and Logical Truth,” The Review of Symbolic Logic, 2: 1–29. (Scholar)
- Brown, Deborah, 2000, “Immanence and Individuation: Brentano and the Scholastics on Knowledge of Singulars,” The Monist, 83: 22–46. (Scholar)
- Caplan, Ben, 2005, “Against Widescopism,” Philosophical Studies, 125: 167–190. (Scholar)
- Carney, James, 1982, “A Kripkean Approach to Aesthetic Theories,” British Journal of Aesthetics, 22: 150–157. (Scholar)
- Cartwright, Richard, 1998, “On Singular Propositions”
in A.A. Kazmi (ed.), Meaning and Reference, Calgary:
University of Calgary Press, pp. 67–83. (Scholar)
- Chalmers, David, 2002, “On Sense and Intension,” Philosophical Perspectives, 16: 135–82. (Scholar)
- –––, 2006, “The Foundations of Two-Dimensional Semantics,” in M. Garcia-Caprintero and J. Macia (eds.), Two-Dimensional Semantics: Foundations and Applications, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Cook, Monte, 1980, “If ‘Cat’ is a Rigid
Designator, What Does it Designate?,” Philosophical
Studies, 37: 61–4. (Scholar)
- Davidson, Matthew, 2003, “Introduction,” in
Plantinga, Essays in the Metaphysics of Modality, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, pp. 3–24. (Scholar)
- Devitt, Michael, 2005, “Rigid Application,” Philosophical Studies, 125: 139–165. (Scholar)
- –––, 2009, “Buenos Aires Symposium on Rigidity: Responses,” Análisis Filosófico, 29: 239–251. (Scholar)
- –––, 2020, “Stirring the Possum: Responses to the Bianchi Papers,” in Andrea Bianchi (ed.), Language and Reality from a Naturalistic Perspective, Philosophical Studies Series, vol 142. Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-47641-0_12">10.1007/978-3-030-47641-0_12">10.1007/978-3-030-47641-0_12 (Scholar)
- Devitt, Michael, and Sterelny, Kim, 1999, Language and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language, 2nd edn. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Donnellan, Keith, 1977, “The Contingent A Priori and Rigid Designators,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 2: 12–27. (Scholar)
- Dranseika, Vilius, Dagys, Jonas and Berniūnas, Renatas, 2020, “Proper Names, Rigidity, and Empirical Studies on Judgments of Identity Across Transformations,” Topoi, 39: 381–388. (Scholar)
- Dummett, Michael, 1981, Frege: Philosophy of Language, 2nd edn. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1991, The Logical Basis of Metaphysics, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Evans, Gareth, 1979, “Reference and Contingency,” Monist, 62: 160–89. (Scholar)
- Everett, Anthony, 2005, “Recent Defenses of Descriptivism,” Mind & Language, 20: 103–39. (Scholar)
- Fara, Delia Graff, 2008, “Relative-Sameness Counterpart Theory,” Review of Symbolic Logic, 1: 167–189. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, “Names are Predicates,” Philosophical Review, 124: 59–117. (Scholar)
- Fitch, G. W., 1976, “Are There Necessary A Posteriori Truths?,” Philosophical Studies, 30: 243–7. (Scholar)
- –––, 2001, “On Theoretical Identifications,” Philosophical Perspectives, 15: 379–92. (Scholar)
- –––, 2004, Saul Kripke, Chesham: Acumen. (Scholar)
- Fitting, Melvin, and Mendelsohn, Richard, 1998, First–Order Modal Logic, Dordrecht: Kluwer. (Scholar)
- Føllesdal, Dagfinn., 1986, “Dagfinn Føllesdal:
Essentialism and Reference,” 97–113 of E.Hahn and P.A. Schilpp,
The Philosophy of WV Quine, LaSalle: Open Court. (Scholar)
- Funkhouser, Eric, 2014, The Logical Structure of Kinds, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Gampel, Eric H., 1997, “Ethics, Reference, and Natural Kinds,” Philosophical Papers, 26: 147–63. (Scholar)
- García-Carpintero Manuel, 2018, “The Mill-Frege Theory of Proper Names,” Mind 127: 1107–1168, doi:10.1093/mind/fzx010. (Scholar)
- Garrett, Brian J., 2005, “Marcus, Ruth Charlotte
Barcan,” in J.R. Shook (ed.), Dictionary of Modern American
Philosophers, London: Continuum International, pp.
1599–1604. (Scholar)
- Gendler, Tamar and Hawthorne, John, 2002, “Introduction,” to Gendler and Hawthorne (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 1–70. (Scholar)
- Gibbard, Allan, 1975, “Contingent Identity,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 4: 187–221. (Scholar)
- Glüer, Kathrin and Pagin, Peter, 2011, “General Terms
and Relational Modality,” Noûs: 1–41. (Scholar)
- Gómez-Torrente, Mario, 2006, “Rigidity and Essentiality,” Mind, 115: 227–259. (Scholar)
- Haukioja, Jussi, 2006, “Proto-Rigidity,” Synthese, 150: 155–169. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, “Rigidity and actuality-dependence,” Philosophical Studies, 157: 399–410. (Scholar)
- Haze, Tristan Grøtvedt, 2021, “A simple theory of rigidity,”
Philosophical Studies. doi:10.1007/s11098-021-01643-y
- Heintz, John, 1973, Subjects and Predicables, Mouton: The Hague. (Scholar)
- Hershenov, David, 2005, “Do Dead Bodies Pose a Problem for Biological Approaches to Personal Identity?,” Mind, 114: 31–59. (Scholar)
- Hughes, Christopher, 2004, Kripke: Names, Necessity, and Identity, Oxford: Clarendon. (Scholar)
- Hunter, David, 2005, “Soames and Widescopism,” Philosophical Studies, 123: 231–241. (Scholar)
- Inan, Ilhan, 2008, “Rigid General Terms and Essential Predicates,” Philosophical Studies, 140: 213–228 (Scholar)
- Jackson, Frank, 1998, From Metaphysics to Ethics, Oxford: Clarendon. (Scholar)
- Justice, John, 2003, “The Semantics of Rigid Designation,” Ratio, 16: 33–48. (Scholar)
- Jylkkä, Jussi, 2008, “Concepts and Reference: Defending a Dual Theory of Natural Kind Concepts,” Ph.D. Disseration, University of Turku, Finland. (Scholar)
- Kaplan, David, 1989a, “Demonstratives,” in J. Almog, H. Wettstein, and J. Perry (eds.), Themes From Kaplan, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 481–563. (Scholar)
- –––, 1989b, “Afterthoughts,” in J. Almog, H. Wettstein, and J. Perry (eds.), Themes From Kaplan, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 565–614. (Scholar)
- King, Jeffrey, 2001, “Day Designators,”
Philosophical Perspectives, 15: 291–333. (Scholar)
- –––, 2001, Complex Demonstratives. Cambridge MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2003, “Tense, Modality, and Semantic Values,” Philosophical Perspectives, pp. 17, 195–245. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, The Nature and Structure of Content, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- King, Peter, 2015, “Thinking About Things: Singular Thought in the Middle Ages” in Gyula Klima (ed.), Intentionality, Cognition and Mental Representation in Medieval Philosophy, New York: Fordham University Press, pp. 104–121. doi:10.5422/fordham/9780823262748.001.0001 [King 2015 available online] (Scholar)
- Kripke, Saul, 1971, “Identity and Necessity,” in M.K. Munitz (ed.), Identity and Individuation, New York: New York University Press, pp. 135–64. (Scholar)
- –––, 1976, “Is There a Problem About Substitutional Quantification?” in Gareth Evans and John McDowell (eds.), Truth and Meaning. Oxford University Press, pp. 324–419. (Scholar)
- –––, 1979, “A Puzzle About Belief,” in A. Margalit (ed.), Meaning and Use, Dordrecht: D. Reidel, pp. 239–83. (Scholar)
- –––, 1980, Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- LaPorte, Joseph, 2003, “Does a Type Specimen Necessarily or Contingently Belong to Its Species?,” Biology and Philosophy, 18: 583–588. (Scholar)
- –––, 2004, Natural Kinds and Conceptual Change, New York: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, Rigid Designation and Theoretical Identities, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2020, “Theoretical Identities as Necessary and A Priori,” In Routledge Handbook on Linguistic Reference, eds. S. Biggs & H. Geirsson. London: Routledge, 324–334. (Scholar)
- Leddy, Thomas, 1987, “Rigid Designation in Defining Art,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 45: 263–272. (Scholar)
- Lee, Jeonggyu, 2020, “Against Predicativism About Names,” Philosophical Studies 177: 243–261. (Scholar)
- Lewis, David, 1986, On the Plurality of Worlds, New York: Basil Blackwell. (Scholar)
- –––, 1998, “Index, Context and
Content,” in Papers in Philosophical Logic, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, pp. 21–44. (Scholar)
- Linsky, Bernard, 1984, “General Terms as Designators,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 65: 259–76. (Scholar)
- Linsky, B., and Zalta, E., 1996, “In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete,” Philosophical Studies, 84: 283–294. (Scholar)
- Locke, John, 1975, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Peter H. Nidditch (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- López de Sa, Dan, 2008, “The Over-Generalization
Problem: Predicates Rigidly Signifying the
‘Unnatural’.” Synthese, 163:
263–272 (Scholar)
- Lowe, E.J., 2008, “Two Notions of Being: Entity and Essence,” Philosophy, 83: 23–48. (Scholar)
- Martí, Genoveva, 1998, “Rigidity and the Description of Counterfactual Situations,” Theoria, 13: 477–90. (Scholar)
- –––, 2003, “The Question of Rigidity in New Theories of Reference,” Noûs 37: 161 –79. (Scholar)
- Matthews, Gareth B., 2005, Augustine, Malden, MA: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Merricks, Trenton, 2001, Objects and Persons, Oxford: Clarendon. (Scholar)
- Meyer, Ulrich, 2013, “Counterpart Theory and the Actuality Operator,” Mind, 122: 27–42. (Scholar)
- Miller, Kristie, 2005, “The Metaphysical Equivalence of Three and Four Dimensionalism,” Erkenntnis, 62: 91–117. (Scholar)
- Nelson, Michael, 2002, “Descriptivism Defended,” Noûs, 36: 408–36. (Scholar)
- Nimtz, Christian, 2019, “Kripkean Meta-Semantics and Generalized Rigidity.” Philosophical Quarterly 69: 332–353. doi:10.1093/pq/pqy059. (Scholar)
- Ninan, Dilip, 2012, “Propositions, Semantic Values, and Rigidity.” Philosophical Studies 158: 401–413. (Scholar)
- Noonan, Harold, 2013, Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Kripke and Naming and Necessity. Oxon: Routledge. (Scholar)
- –––, 2020,“Blackburn’s Supervenience Argument
Against Moral Realism: Revisited,” Metaphysica 21: 151–165, doi:10.1515/mp-2020-0004. (Scholar)
- Nowak, Ethan, 2019, “Complex demonstratives, hidden arguments, and presupposition,” Synthese 198: 1–36. doi:10.1007/s11229-019-02250-5. (Scholar)
- Nunberg, G., 1993, “Indexicality and Deixis,” Linguistics and Philosophy, 16: 1–43. (Scholar)
- Oppy, G., 1994, “Salmon on the Contingent a Priori and the Necessary a Posteriori,” Philosophical Studies, 73: 5–33. (Scholar)
- Plantinga, Alvin, 1974, The Nature of Necessity, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1985, “Self-Profile,” in J.
Tomberlin and P. van Inwagen (eds.), Alvin Plantinga,
Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 3–97. (Scholar)
- –––, 2003, Essays in the Metaphysics of
Modality, Matthew Davidson (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University
Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, Where the Conflict Really Lies. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Putnam, Hilary, 1975, Mind, Language and Reality, New York: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Quinn, Philip L., 1978, “Some Problems about Resurrection,” Religious Studies, 14: 343–59. (Scholar)
- Rabern, B., 2018, “Binding bound variables in epistemic contexts,” Inquiry, 10.1080/0020174X.2018.1470568. (Scholar)
- Rami, Dolf, 2019, “Names and Their Kind of Rigidity,”Erkenntnis, 84: 257–282. (Scholar)
- Rea, Michael (ed.), 1997, Material Constitution, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. (Scholar)
- Robertson, Teresa, 2009, “Essentialism And Reference To
Kinds: Three Issues In Penelope Mackie’s How Things Might Have
Been: Individuals, Kinds, And Essential Properties,”
Philosophical Books, 50: 125–141. (Scholar)
- Russell, Jeffrey, 2013, “Actuality For Counterpart Theorists,” Mind, 122: 85–134. (Scholar)
- Salmon, Nathan, 1981, Reference and Essence, Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1986, Frege’s Puzzle, Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1987–1988, “How to Measure the Standard Metre,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 88: 193–217. (Scholar)
- –––, 2003, “Naming, Necessity, and Beyond,” Mind, 112: 475–92. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, “Are General Terms
Rigid?,” Linguistics and Philosophy, 28:
117–134. (Scholar)
- –––, 2020, “Naming and Non-necessity,” in Andrea Bianchi (ed.), Language and Reality from a Naturalistic Perspective, Philosophical Studies Series, vol 142. Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-47641-0_12 (Scholar)
- Schoubye, Anders, 2018, “The Predicative Predicament,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 96: 571–595. 10.1111/phpr.12336 (Scholar)
- Schwartz, Stephen P., 2002, “Kinds, General Terms, and Rigidity: A Reply to LaPorte,” Philosophical Studies, 109: 265–77. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “Against Rigidity for Natural Kind Terms,” Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-018-1857-x (Scholar)
- –––, 2020, “Against Rigidity for General Terms,” in Andrea Bianchi (ed.), Language and Reality from a Naturalistic Perspective, Philosophical Studies Series, vol 142. Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-47641-0_12 (Scholar)
- Shieh, Sanford, 2001, “Meaning, Rigidity, and
Modality,” in J. Floyd and S. Shieh (eds.), Future Pasts:
the Analytic Tradition in Twentieth Century Philosophy, New York:
Oxford University Press, pp. 369–92. (Scholar)
- Sidelle, Alan, 1992, “Rigidity, Ontology and Semantic Structure,” Journal of Philosophy, 89: 410–30. (Scholar)
- –––, 1995, “A Semantic Account of Rigidity,” Philosophical Studies, 80: 69–105. (Scholar)
- –––, 2002, “Is There a True Metaphysics of Material Objects?” Philosophical Issues, 12 ( Realism and Relativism): 118–145. (Scholar)
- Smith, Quentin, 1989, “The Multiple Uses of Indexicals,” Synthese, 78: 167–191. (Scholar)
- Soames, Scott, 2002, Beyond Rigidity: The Unfinished Semantic Agenda of Naming and Necessity, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, Reference and Description: The Case Against Two-Dimensionalism, Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2006, “Reply to Critics,” Philosophical Studies, 128: 711–38. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, Philosophy of Language, Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
- Sosa, David, 2001, “Rigidity in the Scope of Russell’s
Theory,” Noûs, 35: 1–38. (Scholar)
- Stalnaker, Robert, 2003, Ways a World Might Be, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, Context, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Stanley, Jason, 1997a, “Names and Rigid Designation,” in Bob Hale and Crispin Wright (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 555–85. (Scholar)
- –––, 1997b, “Rigidity and Content,” in R. Heck (ed.), Language, Thought, and Logic: Essays in Honour of Michael Dummett, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 131–56. (Scholar)
- –––, 2002, “Modality and What is Said,” Philosophical Perspectives, 16: 321–44. (Scholar)
- Sullivan, Arthur, 2005, “Rigid, Designation, Direct Reference, and Modal Metaphysics,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 86.4: 577–599. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, Reference and Structure in the Philosophy of Language: A Defense of the Russellian Orthodoxy, New York: Routledge. (Scholar)
- Swinburne, Richard, 2007, “From Mental/Physical Identity to
Substance Dualism,” In Persons Human and Divine, eds.
Peter Van Inwagen and Dean Zimmerman. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
pp. 142–165. (Scholar)
- Torza, Alessandro, 2013, “How to Lewis a Kripke-Hintikka,” Synthese, 190: 743–779. (Scholar)
- Van Fraassen, B., 1984, “Belief and the Will,” The Journal of Philosophy, 81: 235–256. (Scholar)
- Varzi, Achille C., 2003, “Naming the Stages,” Dialectica, 57: 387–412. (Scholar)
- Williamson, T., 2000, “Existence and Contingency,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 100: 117–39. (Scholar)
- –––, 2002, “Necessary Existents,” Logic, Thought and Language, A. O’Hear, (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 233–251. (Scholar)
- Wolter, Lynsey, 2009, “Demonstratives in Philosophy and Linguistics,” Philosophy Compass, 4: 451–68. (Scholar)
- Yalcin, Seth, 2014, “Semantics and Metasemantics in the context of Generative Grammar,” Metasemantics: New Essays on the Foundations of Meaning, eds. A. Burgess and B. Sherman. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 17–54. (Scholar)
- Zagzebski, Linda, 2017, Exemplarist Moral Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Zouhar, Mariá, 2009, “On the Notion of Rigidity for General Terms,” Grazer Philosophische Studien, 78: 207–229. (Scholar)