Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. On the Relationship between the Partition Property and the Weak Partition Property for Normal Ultrafilters on $P_\kappa\lambda^1$.Julius B. Barbanel - 1993 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 58 (1):119-127.
    Suppose $\kappa$ is a supercompact cardinal and $\lambda > \kappa$. We study the relationship between the partition property and the weak partition property for normal ultrafilters on $P_\kappa\lambda$. On the one hand, we show that the following statement is consistent, given an appropriate large cardinal assumption: The partition property and the weak partition property are equivalent, there are many normal ultrafilters that satisfy these properties, and there are many normal ultrafilters that do not satisfy these properties. On the other hand, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Laver Indestructibility and the Class of Compact Cardinals.Arthur W. Apter - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (1):149-157.
    Using an idea developed in joint work with Shelah, we show how to redefine Laver's notion of forcing making a supercompact cardinal $\kappa$ indestructible under $\kappa$-directed closed forcing to give a new proof of the Kimchi-Magidor Theorem in which every compact cardinal in the universe satisfies certain indestructibility properties. Specifically, we show that if K is the class of supercompact cardinals in the ground model, then it is possible to force and construct a generic extension in which the only strongly (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Laver’s results and low-dimensional topology.Patrick Dehornoy - 2016 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 55 (1-2):49-83.
    In connection with his interest in selfdistributive algebra, Richard Laver established two deep results with potential applications in low-dimen\-sional topology, namely the existence of what is now known as the Laver tables and the well-foundedness of the standard ordering of positive braids. Here we present these results and discuss the way they could be used in topological applications.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Another use of set theory.Patrick Dehornoy - 1996 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2 (4):379-391.
    Here, we analyse some recent applications of set theory to topology and argue that set theory is not only the closed domain where mathematics is usually founded, but also a flexible framework where imperfect intuitions can be precisely formalized and technically elaborated before they possibly migrate toward other branches. This apparently new role is mostly reminiscent of the one played by other external fields like theoretical physics, and we think that it could contribute to revitalize the interest in set theory (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • An application of ultrapowers to changing cofinality.Patrick Dehornoy - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (2):225-235.
    If $U_\alpha$ is a length $\omega_1$ sequence of normal ultrafilters on a measurable cardinal $\kappa$ that is increaing w.r.t. the Mitchel order, then the intersection of the $\omega_1$ first iterated ultrapowers of the universe is a Magidor generic extension of the $\omega_1$th iterated ultrapower.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Universal graphs at the successor of a singular cardinal.Mirna Džamonja & Saharon Shelah - 2003 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 68 (2):366-388.
    The paper is concerned with the existence of a universal graph at the successor of a strong limit singular μ of cofinality ℵ0. Starting from the assumption of the existence of a supercompact cardinal, a model is built in which for some such μ there are $\mu^{++}$ graphs on μ+ that taken jointly are universal for the graphs on μ+, while $2^{\mu^+} \gg \mu^{++}$ . The paper also addresses the general problem of obtaining a framework for consistency results at the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Strong ultrapowers and long core models.James Cummings - 1993 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 58 (1):240-248.
  • Possible behaviours for the Mitchell ordering II.James Cummings - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (4):1196-1209.
    We analyse the Mitchell ordering in a model where κ is P 2 κ-hypermeasurable and $2^{2^\kappa} > (2^\kappa)^+$.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The wholeness axiom and Laver sequences.Paul Corazza - 2000 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 105 (1-3):157-260.
    In this paper we introduce the Wholeness Axiom , which asserts that there is a nontrivial elementary embedding from V to itself. We formalize the axiom in the language {∈, j } , adding to the usual axioms of ZFC all instances of Separation, but no instance of Replacement, for j -formulas, as well as axioms that ensure that j is a nontrivial elementary embedding from the universe to itself. We show that WA has consistency strength strictly between I 3 (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Laver sequences for extendible and super-almost-huge cardinals.Paul Corazza - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (3):963-983.
    Versions of Laver sequences are known to exist for supercompact and strong cardinals. Assuming very strong axioms of infinity, Laver sequences can be constructed for virtually any globally defined large cardinal not weaker than a strong cardinal; indeed, under strong hypotheses, Laver sequences can be constructed for virtually any regular class of embeddings. We show here that if there is a regular class of embeddings with critical point κ, and there is an inaccessible above κ, then it is consistent for (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic.Xavier Caicedo, Rolando Chuaqui, Newton C. A. Da Costa & Carlos A. Di Prisco - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (4):1430-1440.
  • Ideals and combinatorial principles.Douglas Burke & Yo Matsubara - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (1):117-122.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Successive large cardinals.Everett L. Bull - 1978 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 15 (2):161.
  • Indestructibility of Vopěnka’s Principle.Andrew D. Brooke-Taylor - 2011 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 50 (5-6):515-529.
    Vopěnka’s Principle is a natural large cardinal axiom that has recently found applications in category theory and algebraic topology. We show that Vopěnka’s Principle and Vopěnka cardinals are relatively consistent with a broad range of other principles known to be independent of standard (ZFC) set theory, such as the Generalised Continuum Hypothesis, and the existence of a definable well-order on the universe of all sets. We achieve this by showing that they are indestructible under a broad class of forcing constructions, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Infinitary combinatorics and modal logic.Andreas Blass - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (2):761-778.
    We show that the modal propositional logic G, originally introduced to describe the modality "it is provable that", is also sound for various interpretations using filters on ordinal numbers, for example the end-segment filters, the club filters, or the ineffable filters. We also prove that G is complete for the interpretation using end-segment filters. In the case of club filters, we show that G is complete if Jensen's principle □ κ holds for all $\kappa ; on the other hand, it (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The weak □* is really weaker than the full □.Shai Ben-David & Menachem Magidor - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (4):1029 - 1033.
  • AD and the supercompactness of ℵ1.Howard Becker - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (4):822-842.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Supercompact cardinals, trees of normal ultrafilters, and the partition property.Julius B. Barbanel - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):701-708.
    Suppose κ is a supercompact cardinal. It is known that for every λ ≥ κ, many normal ultrafilters on P κ (λ) have the partition property. It is also known that certain large cardinal assumptions imply the existence of normal ultrafilters without the partition property. In [1], we introduced the tree T of normal ultrafilters associated with κ. We investigate the distribution throughout T of normal ultrafilters with and normal ultrafilters without the partition property.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Supercompact cardinals and trees of normal ultrafilters.Julius B. Barbanel - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (1):89-109.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Supercompact cardinals, elementary embeddings and fixed points.Julius B. Barbanel - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (1):84-88.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Many-times huge and superhuge cardinals.Julius B. Barbanel, Carlos A. Diprisco & It Beng Tan - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (1):112-122.
  • A note on a result of Kunen and Pelletier.Julius B. Barbanel - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (2):461-465.
    Suppose that U and U' are normal ultrafilters associated with some supercompact cardinal. How may we compare U and U'? In what ways are they similar, and in what ways are they different? Partial answers are given in [1], [2], [3], [5], [6], and [7]. In this paper, we continue this study. In [6], Menas introduced a combinatorial principle χ(U) of normal ultrafilters U associated with supercompact cardinals, and showed that normal ultrafilters satisfying this property also satisfying this property also (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The ⊲-ordering on normal ultrafilters.Stewart Baldwin - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (4):936-952.
  • Generalizing the Mahlo Hierarchy, with Applications to the Mitchell Models.Stewart Baldwin - 1983 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 25 (2):103-127.
  • Between strong and superstrong.Stewart Baldwin - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):547-559.
  • The least strongly compact can be the least strong and indestructible.Arthur W. Apter - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 144 (1-3):33-42.
    We construct two models in which the least strongly compact cardinal κ is also the least strong cardinal. In each of these models, κ satisfies indestructibility properties for both its strong compactness and strongness.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Supercompactness and level by level equivalence are compatible with indestructibility for strong compactness.Arthur W. Apter - 2007 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 46 (3-4):155-163.
    It is known that if $\kappa < \lambda$ are such that κ is indestructibly supercompact and λ is 2λ supercompact, then level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness fails. We prove a theorem which points towards this result being best possible. Specifically, we show that relative to the existence of a supercompact cardinal, there is a model for level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness containing a supercompact cardinal κ in which κ’s strong compactness is indestructible (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Strong Compactness, Square, Gch, and Woodin Cardinals.Arthur W. Apter - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-9.
    We show the consistency, relative to the appropriate supercompactness or strong compactness assumptions, of the existence of a non-supercompact strongly compact cardinal $\kappa _0$ (the least measurable cardinal) exhibiting properties which are impossible when $\kappa _0$ is supercompact. In particular, we construct models in which $\square _{\kappa ^+}$ holds for every inaccessible cardinal $\kappa $ except $\kappa _0$, GCH fails at every inaccessible cardinal except $\kappa _0$, and $\kappa _0$ is less than the least Woodin cardinal.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some remarks on indestructibility and Hamkins? lottery preparation.Arthur W. Apter - 2003 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 42 (8):717-735.
    .In this paper, we first prove several general theorems about strongness, supercompactness, and indestructibility, along the way giving some new applications of Hamkins’ lottery preparation forcing to indestructibility. We then show that it is consistent, relative to the existence of cardinals κ<λ so that κ is λ supercompact and λ is inaccessible, for the least strongly compact cardinal κ to be the least strong cardinal and to have its strongness, but not its strong compactness, indestructible under κ-strategically closed forcing.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Tallness and level by level equivalence and inequivalence.Arthur W. Apter - 2010 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 56 (1):4-12.
    We construct two models containing exactly one supercompact cardinal in which all non-supercompact measurable cardinals are strictly taller than they are either strongly compact or supercompact. In the first of these models, level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness holds. In the other, level by level inequivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness holds. Each universe has only one strongly compact cardinal and contains relatively few large cardinals.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Precisely controlling level by level behavior.Arthur W. Apter - 2017 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 63 (1-2):77-84.
    We construct four models containing one supercompact cardinal in which level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness and level by level inequivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness are precisely controlled at each non‐supercompact measurable cardinal. In these models, no cardinal κ is ‐supercompact, where is the least inaccessible cardinal greater than κ.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On measurable limits of compact cardinals.Arthur W. Apter - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (4):1675-1688.
    We extend earlier work (both individual and joint with Shelah) and prove three theorems about the class of measurable limits of compact cardinals, where a compact cardinal is one which is either strongly compact or supercompact. In particular, we construct two models in which every measurable limit of compact cardinals below the least supercompact limit of supercompact cardinals possesses non-trivial degrees of supercompactness. In one of these models, every measurable limit of compact cardinals is a limit of supercompact cardinals and (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Patterns of compact cardinals.Arthur W. Apter - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 89 (2-3):101-115.
    We show relative to strong hypotheses that patterns of compact cardinals in the universe, where a compact cardinal is one which is either strongly compact or supercompact, can be virtually arbitrary. Specifically, we prove if V “ZFC + Ω is the least inaccessible limit of measurable limits of supercompact cardinals + ƒ : Ω → 2 is a function”, then there is a partial ordering P V so that for , There is a proper class of compact cardinals + If (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Normal measures on a tall cardinal.Arthur W. Apter & James Cummings - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (1):178-204.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Measurability and degrees of strong compactness.Arthur W. Apter - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (2):249-254.
    We prove, relative to suitable hypotheses, that it is consistent for there to be unboundedly many measurable cardinals each of which possesses a large degree of strong compactness, and that it is consistent to assume that the least measurable is partially strongly compact and that the second measurable is strongly compact. These results partially answer questions of Magidor on the relationship of strong compactness to measurability.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Indestructible strong compactness but not supercompactness.Arthur W. Apter, Moti Gitik & Grigor Sargsyan - 2012 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (9):1237-1242.
  • Indestructibility, instances of strong compactness, and level by level inequivalence.Arthur W. Apter - 2010 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 49 (7-8):725-741.
    Suppose λ > κ is measurable. We show that if κ is either indestructibly supercompact or indestructibly strong, then A = {δ < κ | δ is measurable, yet δ is neither δ + strongly compact nor a limit of measurable cardinals} must be unbounded in κ. The large cardinal hypothesis on λ is necessary, as we further demonstrate by constructing via forcing two models in which ${A = \emptyset}$ . The first of these contains a supercompact cardinal κ and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Indestructible strong compactness and level by level inequivalence.Arthur W. Apter - 2013 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 59 (4-5):371-377.
    If are such that δ is indestructibly supercompact and γ is measurable, then it must be the case that level by level inequivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness fails. We prove a theorem which points to this result being best possible. Specifically, we show that relative to the existence of cardinals such that κ1 is λ‐supercompact and λ is inaccessible, there is a model for level by level inequivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness containing a supercompact cardinal in which κ’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Indestructibility under adding Cohen subsets and level by level equivalence.Arthur W. Apter - 2009 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 55 (3):271-279.
    We construct a model for the level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness in which the least supercompact cardinal κ has its strong compactness indestructible under adding arbitrarily many Cohen subsets. There are no restrictions on the large cardinal structure of our model.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Level by level equivalence and strong compactness.Arthur W. Apter - 2004 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 50 (1):51.
    We force and construct models in which there are non-supercompact strongly compact cardinals which aren't measurable limits of strongly compact cardinals and in which level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness holds non-trivially except at strongly compact cardinals. In these models, every measurable cardinal κ which isn't either strongly compact or a witness to a certain phenomenon first discovered by Menas is such that for every regular cardinal λ > κ, κ is λ strongly compact iff κ is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Filter spaces: towards a unified theory of large cardinal and embedding axioms.Arthur Apter, Carlos Diprisco, James Henle & William Swicker - 1989 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 41 (2):93-106.
  • Indestructibility and level by level equivalence and inequivalence.Arthur W. Apter - 2007 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 53 (1):78-85.
    If κ < λ are such that κ is indestructibly supercompact and λ is 2λ supercompact, it is known from [4] that {δ < κ | δ is a measurable cardinal which is not a limit of measurable cardinals and δ violates level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness}must be unbounded in κ. On the other hand, using a variant of the argument used to establish this fact, it is possible to prove that if κ < λ are (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Indestructibility and destructible measurable cardinals.Arthur W. Apter - 2016 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 55 (1-2):3-18.
    Say that κ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\kappa}$$\end{document}’s measurability is destructible if there exists a κ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\kappa}$$\end{document}. It then follows that A1={δ<κ∣δ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${A_{1} = \{\delta < \kappa \mid \delta}$$\end{document} is measurable, δ is not a limit of measurable cardinals, δ is not δ+ strongly compact, and δ’s measurability is destructible when forcing with partial orderings having rank below λδ} is unbounded (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Indestructibility and stationary reflection.Arthur W. Apter - 2009 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 55 (3):228-236.
    If κ < λ are such that κ is a strong cardinal whose strongness is indestructible under κ -strategically closed forcing and λ is weakly compact, then we show thatA = {δ < κ | δ is a non-weakly compact Mahlo cardinal which reflects stationary sets}must be unbounded in κ. This phenomenon, however, need not occur in a universe with relatively few large cardinals. In particular, we show how to construct a model where no cardinal is supercompact up to a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Identity crises and strong compactness.Arthur W. Apter & James Cummings - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (4):1895-1910.
    Combining techniques of the first author and Shelah with ideas of Magidor, we show how to get a model in which, for fixed but arbitrary finite n, the first n strongly compact cardinals κ 1 ,..., κ n are so that κ i for i = 1,..., n is both the i th measurable cardinal and κ + i supercompact. This generalizes an unpublished theorem of Magidor and answers a question of Apter and Shelah.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Identity crises and strong compactness III: Woodin cardinals. [REVIEW]Arthur W. Apter & Grigor Sargsyan - 2006 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 45 (3):307-322.
    We show that it is consistent, relative to n ∈ ω supercompact cardinals, for the strongly compact and measurable Woodin cardinals to coincide precisely. In particular, it is consistent for the first n strongly compact cardinals to be the first n measurable Woodin cardinals, with no cardinal above the n th strongly compact cardinal being measurable. In addition, we show that it is consistent, relative to a proper class of supercompact cardinals, for the strongly compact cardinals and the cardinals which (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Diamond, square, and level by level equivalence.Arthur W. Apter - 2005 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 44 (3):387-395.
    We force and construct a model in which level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness holds, along with certain additional combinatorial properties. In particular, in this model, ♦ δ holds for every regular uncountable cardinal δ, and below the least supercompact cardinal κ, □ δ holds on a stationary subset of κ. There are no restrictions in our model on the structure of the class of supercompact cardinals.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Exactly controlling the non-supercompact strongly compact cardinals.Arthur W. Apter & Joel David Hamkins - 2003 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 68 (2):669-688.
    We summarize the known methods of producing a non-supercompact strongly compact cardinal and describe some new variants. Our Main Theorem shows how to apply these methods to many cardinals simultaneously and exactly control which cardinals are supercompact and which are only strongly compact in a forcing extension. Depending upon the method, the surviving non-supercompact strongly compact cardinals can be strong cardinals, have trivial Mitchell rank or even contain a club disjoint from the set of measurable cardinals. These results improve and (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Failures of SCH and Level by Level Equivalence.Arthur W. Apter - 2006 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 45 (7):831-838.
    We construct a model for the level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness in which below the least supercompact cardinal κ, there is a stationary set of cardinals on which SCH fails. In this model, the structure of the class of supercompact cardinals can be arbitrary.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Consecutive Singular Cardinals and the Continuum Function.Arthur W. Apter & Brent Cody - 2013 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 54 (2):125-136.
    We show that from a supercompact cardinal $\kappa$, there is a forcing extension $V[G]$ that has a symmetric inner model $N$ in which $\mathrm {ZF}+\lnot\mathrm {AC}$ holds, $\kappa$ and $\kappa^{+}$ are both singular, and the continuum function at $\kappa$ can be precisely controlled, in the sense that the final model contains a sequence of distinct subsets of $\kappa$ of length equal to any predetermined ordinal. We also show that the above situation can be collapsed to obtain a model of $\mathrm (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation