The dependence of computability on numerical notations

Synthese 198 (11):10485-10511 (2021)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Which function is computed by a Turing machine will depend on how the symbols it manipulates are interpreted. Further, by invoking bizarre systems of notation it is easy to define Turing machines that compute textbook examples of uncomputable functions, such as the solution to the decision problem for first-order logic. Thus, the distinction between computable and uncomputable functions depends on the system of notation used. This raises the question: which systems of notation are the relevant ones for determining whether a function is computable? These are the acceptable notations. I argue for a use criterion of acceptability: the acceptable notations for a domain of objects D\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\mathcal {D}}$$\end{document} are the notations that we can use for the usual D\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\mathcal {D}}$$\end{document}-activities. Acceptable notations for natural numbers are ones that we can count with. Acceptable notations for logical formulas are the ones that we can use in inference and logical analysis. And so on. This criterion makes computability a relative notion—whether a function is computable depends on which notations are acceptable, which is relative to our interests and abilities. I argue that this is not a problem, however, since there is independent reason for taking the extension of computable function to be relative to contingent facts. Similarly, the fact that the use criterion makes a mathematical distinction depend on practical concerns is also not a problem because it dovetails with similar phenomena in other areas of computability theory, namely the roles of notation in computation over real numbers and of Extended Church’s Thesis in complexity theory.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 93,127

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Index sets and Scott sentences.J. F. Knight & C. McCoy - 2014 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 53 (5-6):519-524.
Strongly unbounded and strongly dominating sets of reals generalized.Michal Dečo - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (7-8):825-838.
Comparison of fine structural mice via coarse iteration.F. Schlutzenberg & J. R. Steel - 2014 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 53 (5-6):539-559.
Two-cardinal diamond and games of uncountable length.Pierre Matet - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (3-4):395-412.

Analytics

Added to PP
2020-06-18

Downloads
18 (#860,222)

6 months
3 (#1,046,015)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

References found in this work

Introduction to metamathematics.Stephen Cole Kleene - 1952 - Groningen: P. Noordhoff N.V..
On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem.Alan Turing - 1936 - Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society 42 (1):230-265.
Computability & unsolvability.Martin Davis - 1958 - New York: Dover Publications.
Computability and Logic.G. S. Boolos & R. C. Jeffrey - 1977 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 28 (1):95-95.

View all 32 references / Add more references