‘But not that which has lost its soul is what is potentially alive’ – The Relation between Body and Soul in Aristotle

Ancient Philosophy Today 5 (1):29-54 (2023)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The thus far little noticed element in Aristotle's definition of the soul – namely, its nexus to the particularities of a complex physical body (σῶμα φυσικόν / sôma physikon) – is the key to resolve three apparent inconsistencies of Aristotelian hylomorphism: First, the incompatible modalities of the assumed binding relation between physical body as a simultaneously functional matter and the soul as its form; second, the homonymy problem, i.e., that, according to Aristotle's own statement, a body’s remnant that was abandoned by its soul can only homonymously be called that which it was when it was alive; third, the problem that form in hylomorphism seems to be nothing but a configuration of material parts, which, though conceptualised in abstraction and independent from matter, would nevertheless add nothing new to the material composition in which it is instantiated. If that were so, how, then, can a hylomorphic theory conceive of form as ontologically separate from matter? Without a comprehensive and comprehensible resolution of those three major aporias – that is in line with today’s scientific conception of the world – Aristotle’s definition of the soul as form-without-matter would, in Ackrill's words, ‘resist interpretation’. This paper shows that such a resolution can in fact be achieved and that Aristotle’s hylomorphism allows for a plausible and consistent interpretation.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 93,127

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Aristotle and Functionalism.Corinne Painter - 2004 - Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 9 (1):53-77.
Homonymy and the Matter of a Living Body.Christopher V. Mirus - 2001 - Ancient Philosophy 21 (2):357-373.
Intellectual Abstraction in St. Albert.Herbert Johnston - 1960 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 10 (10):204-212.
Aquinas and Aristotelian Hylomorphism.Raymond Hain - 2015 - In Matthew Levering & Gilles Emery (eds.), Aristotle in Aquinas’s Theology. Oxford University Press. pp. 48-69.
Klasyczny i współczesny hylemorfizm a dusza ludzka.Mariusz Tabaczek - 2019 - Roczniki Filozoficzne 67 (1):149-176.
The Soul-Body Relation in Philosophy and Gnosis.Mukhtar Izadi - unknown - Kheradnameh Sadra Quarterly 29.
The Soul as Substance.Terence Irwin - 1988 - In Aristotle's first principles. New York: Oxford University Press.

Analytics

Added to PP
2023-03-26

Downloads
28 (#589,033)

6 months
18 (#152,778)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Thomas Buchheim
Ludwig Maximilians Universität, München

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Aristotle.Christopher Shields - 2007 - In . Routledge.
Contemporary Hylomorphisms: On the Matter of Form.Christopher J. Austin - 2020 - Ancient Philosophy Today 2 (2):113-144.
Aristotle's Definitions of Psuche.J. L. Ackrill - 1973 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 73:119 - 133.
Aristotle and the Mind-Body Problem.Robert Heinaman - 1990 - Phronesis 35 (1):83-102.

View all 17 references / Add more references