Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Can the Classical Logician Avoid the Revenge Paradoxes?Andrew Bacon - 2015 - Philosophical Review 124 (3):299-352.
    Most work on the semantic paradoxes within classical logic has centered around what this essay calls “linguistic” accounts of the paradoxes: they attribute to sentences or utterances of sentences some property that is supposed to explain their paradoxical or nonparadoxical status. “No proposition” views are paradigm examples of linguistic theories, although practically all accounts of the paradoxes subscribe to some kind of linguistic theory. This essay shows that linguistic accounts of the paradoxes endorsing classical logic are subject to a particularly (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Lies, lies, and more lies: A plea for propositions.Jordan Howard Sobel - 1992 - Philosophical Studies 67 (1):51-69.
    To resolve putative liar paradoxes it is sufficient to attend to the distinction between liar-sentences and the propositions they would express, and to exercise the option of turning would-be deductions of paradox (of contradictions) into reductions of the existence of those propositions. Defending the coherence of particular resolutions along these lines, leads to recognition of the non-extensionality of some liar-sentences. In particular, it turns out that exchanges of terms for identicals in the open-sentence '- does not expression a true proposition' (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Are Propositions Essentially Representational?Bryan Pickel - 2017 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 98 (3).
    Jeffrey King argues that nothing has truth conditions except by being taken to be true or false by rational agents. But – for good reason – King claims that propositions possess truth conditions essentially and intrinsically. I will argue that King cannot have both: if the truth conditions of a proposition depend on the reactions of rational agents, then the possession of truth conditions can't follow from the intrinsic nature or existence of the proposition. This leaves two options. Either, nothing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Chrysippus intuition and contextual theories of truth.Jay Newhard - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 142 (3):345-352.
    Contextual theories of truth are motivated primarily by the resolution they provide to paradoxical reasoning about truth. The principal argument for contextual theories of truth relies on a key intuition about the truth value of the proposition expressed by a particular utterance made during paradoxical reasoning, which Anil Gupta calls “the Chrysippus intuition.” In this paper, I argue that the principal argument for contextual theories of truth is circular, and that the Chrysippus intuition is false. I conclude that the philosophical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Bhart $$\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{R} $$ hari's solution to the liar and some other paradoxeshari's solution to the liar and some other paradoxes. [REVIEW]Jan E. M. Houben - 1995 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 23 (4):381-401.
  • Dynamic semantics and circular propositions.Willem Groeneveld - 1994 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 23 (3):267 - 306.