The Skeptic's Progress: Austin, Wittgenstein, and Contemporary Approaches to Skepticism

Dissertation, The University of Chicago (1995)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The resurgent interest in skepticism over the past fifteen years is due largely to perceived breakthroughs by Robert Nozick and Stanley Cavell, who each question skeptical assumptions thought to have gone unquestioned since Descartes. I argue that Austin and Wittgenstein each questioned the same assumptions over forty years ago, that they did so in a more complete and convincing manner, and that their approaches to skepticism, properly understood, are as sophisticated and compelling as any yet produced. ;In Philosophical Explanations, Nozick questions the assumption that to accept the possibility of skeptical hypotheses is to reject the possibility of knowledge of the external world. He claims that this implication holds only if the closure principle holds, and argues that the closure principle fails. I maintain that the skeptic's reasoning doesn't depend on the closure principle, that it depends instead on a stronger "infallibility" principle, and that Nozick's arguments against the closure principle are, in any case, unacceptably weak. I then explicate and defend strong arguments in both Austin and Wittgenstein against the skeptic's use of the infallibility principle. ;In The Claim of Reason, Cavell shows how the skeptic attempts to cast doubt on the whole of our knowledge by casting doubt on a "best case" claim to knowledge--a claim which we cannot place in doubt without thereby placing in doubt every other claim to knowledge. He then questions the assumption that there can be best case claims, providing a "schema" for showing that what the skeptic takes as a best case claim is not, grammatically, a claim at all. I argue that Austin and Wittgenstein anticipate Cavell in asserting the incoherence of the notion of a best case claim, and that jointly they provide a framework within which Cavell's schema can be brought to fruition

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,709

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Knowledge and deductive closure.James L. White - 1991 - Synthese 86 (3):409 - 423.
Peirce, Wittgenstein y Davidson: coincidencias anti-escépticas.Daniel Kalpokas - 2008 - Areté. Revista de Filosofía 20 (2):217-232.
The Relevance of Skepticism.James Markham Ambler Bell - 2002 - Dissertation, University of Michigan
Can contextualists maintain neutrality?Martin Montminy - 2008 - Philosophers' Imprint 8:1-13.
What We Can Learn from the Skeptical Puzzle.Tim Black - 2009 - Iris. European Journal of Philosophy and Public Debate 1 (2):439-447.
Two skeptical arguments or only one?Kevin McCain - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 164 (2):289-300.
In Conversation with the Skeptic: Contextualism and the Raising of Standards.Daniele Sgaravatti - 2013 - International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 3 (2):97-118.

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-02-04

Downloads
0

6 months
0

Historical graph of downloads

Sorry, there are not enough data points to plot this chart.
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references