Desires, Values and Norms

In Federico Lauria & Julien Deonna (eds.), The Nature of Desire. Oxford University Press. pp. 352 (2017)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The thesis defended, the “guise of the ought”, is that the formal objects of desires are norms (oughts to be or oughts to do) rather than values (as the “guise of the good” thesis has it). It is impossible, in virtue of the nature of desire, to desire something without it being presented as something that ought to be or that one ought to do. This view is defended by pointing to a key distinction between values and norms: positive and negative norms (obligation and interdiction) are interdefinable through negation; positive and negative values aren’t. This contrast between the norms and values, it is argued, is mirrored, within the psychological realm, by the contrast between the desires and emotions. Positive and negative desires are interdefinable through negation, but positive and negative emotions aren’t. The overall, Meinongian picture suggested is that norms are to desires what values are to emotions.

Links

PhilArchive

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Waarden en normen, idealen en principes.Herman De Dijn - 1996 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 58 (2):261-276.
The Structure of Values and Norms.Sven Ove Hansson - 2001 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
Desires and reasons.Alan Goldman - 2009 - American Philosophical Quarterly 46 (4):291 - 304.
Reasons From The Humean Perspective.Elizabeth S. Radcliffe - 2012 - Philosophical Quarterly 62 (249):777-796.
Moore’s paradox in belief and desire.John N. Williams - 2014 - Acta Analytica 29 (1):1-23.
Desires without Guises: Why We Need Not Value What We Want.Sabine Döring & Bahadir Eker - forthcoming - In Julien Deonna & Federico Lauria (eds.), The Nature of Desire. Oxford University Press.
Epistemic normativity.Hilary Kornblith - 1993 - Synthese 94 (3):357 - 376.
On the Subjectivity of Values.Anthony Ernest Weston - 1982 - Dissertation, University of Michigan
Desire, Duty and Moral Absolutes.Antony Duff - 1980 - Philosophy 55 (212):223 - 238.
Normativity and Judgement.Julia Tanney - 1999 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 73 (1):17 - 61.
Normativity and judgement: Julia Tanney.Julia Tanney - 1999 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 73 (1):45–61.

Analytics

Added to PP
2016-05-03

Downloads
617 (#28,008)

6 months
161 (#20,231)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Olivier Massin
Université de Neuchâtel

Citations of this work

Desire-As-Belief and Evidence Sensitivity.Kael McCormack - 2023 - Theoria. An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science 38 (2):155-172.
Intelligibility and the Guise of the Good.Paul Boswell - 2018 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 13 (1):1-31.
Emotional Phenomenology: Toward a Nonreductive Analysis.Arnaud Dewalque - 2017 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 41 (1):27-40.
A Disjunctive Account of Desire.Kael McCormack - 2022 - Dissertation, University of New South Wales

View all 6 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Rationality Through Reasoning.John Broome (ed.) - 2013 - Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
Leviathan.Thomas Hobbes - 1651 - Harmondsworth,: Penguin Books. Edited by C. B. Macpherson.
Essence and modality.Kit Fine - 1994 - Philosophical Perspectives 8 (Logic and Language):1-16.
A Natural History of Negation.Laurence R. Horn - 1989 - University of Chicago Press.
Value in ethics and economics.Elizabeth Anderson - 1993 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

View all 71 references / Add more references