Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A Virtue Ethics Approach to Aldo Leopold’s Land Ethic.Bill Shaw - 1997 - Environmental Ethics 19 (1):53-67.
    I examine “The Land Ethic” by Aldo Leopold from a virtue ethics perspective. Following Leopold, I posit the “good” as the “integrity, stability, and beauty” of biotic communities and then develop “land virtues” that foster this good. I recommend and defend three land virtues: respect, prudence, and practical judgment.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Just garbage.Peter S. Wenz - 2009 - In Craig Hanks (ed.), Technology and values: essential readings. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Virtues of Stewardship.Jennifer Welchman - 1999 - Environmental Ethics 21 (4):411-423.
    What virtues do good stewards typically have and can these virtues move people to be good stewards of nature? Why focus on the virtues of stewards rather than on trying to construct and defend morally obligatory rules to govern human behavior? I argue that benevolence and loyalty are crucial for good stewardship and these virtues can and do motivate people to act as good stewards of nature. Moreover,since it is a matter of dispute whether rational considerations can move us to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Environmental philosophy after the end of nature.Steven Vogel - 2002 - Environmental Ethics 24 (1):23-39.
    I call for “postnaturalism” in environmental philosophy—for an environmental philosophy that no longer employs the concept nature. First, the term is too ambiguous and philosophically dangerous and, second, McKibben and others who argue that nature has already ended are probably right—except that perhaps nature has always already ended. Poststructuralism, environmental history, and recent science studies all point in the same direction: the world we inhabit is always already one transformed by human practices. Environmental questions are social and political ones, to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Environmental Philosophy after the End of Nature.Steven Vogel - 2002 - Environmental Ethics 24 (1):23-39.
    I call for “postnaturalism” in environmental philosophy—for an environmental philosophy that no longer employs the concept nature. First, the term is too ambiguous and philosophically dangerous and, second, McKibben and others who argue that nature has already ended are probably right—except that perhaps nature has always already ended. Poststructuralism, environmental history, and recent science studies all point in the same direction: the world we inhabit is always already one transformed by human practices. Environmental questions are social and political ones, to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics - 25th Anniversary Edition.Paul W. Taylor (ed.) - 1986
    What rational justification is there for conceiving of all living things as possessing inherent worth? In _Respect for Nature_, Paul Taylor draws on biology, moral philosophy, and environmental science to defend a biocentric environmental ethic in which all life has value. Without making claims for the moral rights of plants and animals, he offers a reasoned alternative to the prevailing anthropocentric view--that the natural environment and its wildlife are valued only as objects for human use or enjoyment. _Respect for Nature_ (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   236 citations  
  • Our vision for the agricultural sciences need not include biotechnology.Wes Jackson - 1991 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 4 (2):207-215.
  • Ideals of Human Excellence and Preserving Natural Environments.Thomas E. Hill Jr - 1983 - Environmental Ethics 5 (3):211-224.
    The moral significance of preserving natural environments is not entirely an issue of rights and social utility, for a person’s attitude toward nature may be importantly connected with virtues or human excellences. The question is, “What sort of person would destroy the natural environment--or even see its value solely in cost/benefit terms?” The answer I suggest is that willingness to do so may well reveal the absence of traits which are a natural basis for a proper humility, self-acceptance, gratitude, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • What is Environmental Virtue Ethics That We Should Be Mindful of It?Geoffrey B. Frasz - 2001 - Philosophy in the Contemporary World 8 (2):5-14.
    There has been increased interest in developing what I call environmental virtue ethics (EVE). This paper presents some of the centralfeatures of this project. The first part is a general description of EVE, showing why there is a need for it. The second part spells out the central features of EVE including an account of the good life as flourishing in an expanded or mixed biotic community, and provides a tentative list of important environmental virtues. The third part examines one (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Environmental Virtue Ethics.Geoffrey B. Frasz - 1993 - Environmental Ethics 15 (3):259-274.
    In this essay, I first extend the insights of virtue ethics into environmental ethics and examine the possible dangers of this approach. Second, I analyze some qualities of character that an environmentally virtuous person must possess. Third, I evaluate “humility” as an environmental virtue, specifically, the position of Thomas E. Hill, Jr. I conclude that Hill’s conception of “proper” humility can be more adequatelyexplicated by associating it with another virtue, environmental “openness.”.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Environmental Virtue Ethics.Geoffrey B. Frasz - 1993 - Environmental Ethics 15 (3):259-274.
    In this essay, I first extend the insights of virtue ethics into environmental ethics and examine the possible dangers of this approach. Second, I analyze some qualities of character that an environmentally virtuous person must possess. Third, I evaluate “humility” as an environmental virtue, specifically, the position of Thomas E. Hill, Jr. I conclude that Hill’s conception of “proper” humility can be more adequatelyexplicated by associating it with another virtue, environmental “openness.”.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • On Environmental Virtue Ethics.Ron Erickson - 1994 - Environmental Ethics 16 (3):334-336.
  • Thoreau, Leopold, and Carson.Philip Cafaro - 2001 - Environmental Ethics 23 (1):3-17.
    I argue for an environmental virtue ethics which specifies human excellence and flourishing in relation to nature. I consider Henry David Thoreau, Aldo Leopold, and Rachel Carson as environmental virtue ethicists, and show that these writers share certain ethical positions that any environmental virtue ethics worthy of the name must embrace. These positions include putting economic life in its proper,subordinate place within human life as a whole; cultivating scientific knowledge, while appreciating its limits; extending moral considerability to the nonhuman world; (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations