Why Husserl’s Universal Empiricism is a Moderate Rationalism

Axiomathes 28 (5):539-563 (2018)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Husserl claims that his phenomenological–epistemological system amounts to a “universal” form of empiricism. The present paper shows that this universal moment of Husserl’s empiricism is why his empiricism qualifies as a rationalism. What is empiricist about Husserl’s phenomenological–epistemological system is that he takes experiences to be an autonomous source of immediate justification. On top of that, Husserl takes experiences to be the ultimate source of justification. For Husserl, every justified belief ultimately depends epistemically on the subject’s experiences. These are paradigms of empiricist claims and thus Husserl seems to subscribe to empiricism. However, what is universal about Husserl’s “empiricism” is that he does not limit the concept of experiences to sensory experiences or sensory experiences plus introspective intuitions but broadens the concept of experience such that also a priori intuitions are included. Husserl insists that logical, mathematical, and phenomenological intuitions such as ~, 2 + 2 = 4, and “Experiences necessarily bear the mark of intentionality” provide non-inferential justification analogous to how sensory experiences can non-inferentially justify beliefs such as “There is a table in front of me.” Importantly, Husserl makes clear that such a priori intuitions are not about our concepts but about reality. This is why Husserl’s universal empiricism is a rationalism. Husserl differs from traditional rationalism as he allows that a priori intuitions can be fallible and empirically underminable. This distinguishes Husserl’s rationalism from Descartes’ and makes him a proponent of moderate rationalism as currently championed by Laurence BonJour.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,592

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Husserl’s Critique of Kant’s Ethics.Henning Peucker - 2007 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 45 (2):309-319.
Husserl and externalism.A. David Smith - 2008 - Synthese 160 (3):313-333.
Die Phänomenologie als radikaler Empirismus.Vittorio De Palma - 2012 - Studia Phaenomenologica 12:331-357.
Apriori and world: European contributions to Husserlian phenomenology.William R. McKenna, Robert M. Harlan & Laurence E. Winters (eds.) - 1981 - Hingham, MA: distributors for the U.S. and Canada, Kluwer Boston.
The incoherence of empiricism.George Bealer - 1992 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 66 (1):99-138.
Husserls Dualismus.Uwe Meixner - 2007 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 10.
Husserls Dualismus.Uwe Meixner - 2007 - E-Journal Philosophie der Psychologie 9.
Husserl’s Evidence Problem.Ülker Öktem - 2009 - Indo-Pacific Journal of Phenomenology 9 (1):1-14.
The Consistency of Husserl's Theory of Meaning.Matt Taylor - 2000 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 60 (1):171-195.

Analytics

Added to PP
2018-07-05

Downloads
62 (#258,501)

6 months
14 (#175,523)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Philipp Berghofer
University of Graz

References found in this work

The Philosophy of Philosophy.Timothy Williamson - 2007 - Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences.Eugene Wigner - 1960 - Communications in Pure and Applied Mathematics 13:1-14.
Modal Epistemology and the Rationalist Renaissance.George Bealer - 2002 - In Tamar Szabo Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility. Oxford University Press. pp. 71-125.
Intuitions as evidence.Joel Pust - 2000 - New York: Garland.

View all 45 references / Add more references