Results for ' bounded Turing degrees'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  14
    A Bounded Jump for the Bounded Turing Degrees.Bernard Anderson & Barbara Csima - 2014 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 55 (2):245-264.
    We define the bounded jump of $A$ by $A^{b}=\{x\in \omega \mid \exists i\leq x[\varphi_{i}\downarrow \wedge\Phi_{x}^{A\upharpoonright \!\!\!\upharpoonright \varphi_{i}}\downarrow ]\}$ and let $A^{nb}$ denote the $n$th bounded jump. We demonstrate several properties of the bounded jump, including the fact that it is strictly increasing and order-preserving on the bounded Turing degrees. We show that the bounded jump is related to the Ershov hierarchy. Indeed, for $n\geq2$ we have $X\leq_{bT}\emptyset ^{nb}\iff X$ is $\omega^{n}$-c.e. $\iff X\leq_{1}\emptyset ^{nb}$, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  2.  12
    On the strongly bounded turing degrees of simple sets.Klaus Ambos-Spies - 2014 - In On the strongly bounded turing degrees of simple sets. pp. 23-78.
  3.  41
    Upper bounds on ideals in the computably enumerable Turing degrees.George Barmpalias & André Nies - 2011 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (6):465-473.
    We study ideals in the computably enumerable Turing degrees, and their upper bounds. Every proper ideal in the c.e. Turing degrees has an incomplete upper bound. It follows that there is no prime ideal in the c.e. Turing degrees. This answers a question of Calhoun [2]. Every proper ideal in the c.e. Turing degrees has a low2 upper bound. Furthermore, the partial order of ideals under inclusion is dense.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4. More about uniform upper Bounds on ideals of Turing degrees.Harold T. Hodes - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (2):441-457.
    Let I be a countable jump ideal in $\mathscr{D} = \langle \text{The Turing degrees}, \leq\rangle$ . The central theorem of this paper is: a is a uniform upper bound on I iff a computes the join of an I-exact pair whose double jump a (1) computes. We may replace "the join of an I-exact pair" in the above theorem by "a weak uniform upper bound on I". We also answer two minimality questions: the class of uniform upper bounds (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Upper bounds on locally countable admissible initial segments of a Turing degree hierarchy.Harold T. Hodes - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (4):753-760.
    Where AR is the set of arithmetic Turing degrees, 0 (ω ) is the least member of { $\mathbf{\alpha}^{(2)}|\mathbf{a}$ is an upper bound on AR}. This situation is quite different if we examine HYP, the set of hyperarithmetic degrees. We shall prove (Corollary 1) that there is an a, an upper bound on HYP, whose hyperjump is the degree of Kleene's O. This paper generalizes this example, using an iteration of the jump operation into the transfinite which (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6. Uniform Upper Bounds on Ideals of Turing Degrees.Harold T. Hodes - 1978 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 43 (3):601-612.
  7.  14
    A Minimal Upper Bound on a Sequence of Turing Degrees Which Represents that Sequence.Harold T. Hodes - 1983 - Pacific Journal of Mathematics 108 (1):115-119.
  8.  14
    On relative enumerability of Turing degrees.Shamil Ishmukhametov - 2000 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 39 (3):145-154.
    Let d be a Turing degree, R[d] and Q[d] denote respectively classes of recursively enumerable (r.e.) and all degrees in which d is relatively enumerable. We proved in Ishmukhametov [1999] that there is a degree d containing differences of r.e.sets (briefly, d.r.e.degree) such that R[d] possess a least elementm $>$ 0. Now we show the existence of a d.r.e. d such that R[d] has no a least element. We prove also that for any REA-degree d below 0 $'$ (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  65
    Randomness, relativization and Turing degrees.André Nies, Frank Stephan & Sebastiaan A. Terwijn - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (2):515-535.
    We compare various notions of algorithmic randomness. First we consider relativized randomness. A set is n-random if it is Martin-Löf random relative to ∅. We show that a set is 2-random if and only if there is a constant c such that infinitely many initial segments x of the set are c-incompressible: C ≥ |x|-c. The ‘only if' direction was obtained independently by Joseph Miller. This characterization can be extended to the case of time-bounded C-complexity. Next we prove some (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  10.  20
    A minimal pair joining to a plus cupping Turing degree.Dengfeng Li & Angsheng Li - 2003 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 49 (6):553-566.
    A computably enumerable degree a is called nonbounding, if it bounds no minimal pair, and plus cupping, if every nonzero c.e. degree x below a is cuppable. Let NB and PC be the sets of all nonbounding and plus cupping c.e. degrees, respectively. Both NB and PC are well understood, but it has not been possible so far to distinguish between the two classes. In the present paper, we investigate the relationship between the classes NB and PC, and show (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  59
    Eventually infinite time Turing machine degrees: Infinite time decidable reals.P. D. Welch - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (3):1193-1203.
    We characterise explicitly the decidable predicates on integers of Infinite Time Turing machines, in terms of admissibility theory and the constructible hierarchy. We do this by pinning down ζ, the least ordinal not the length of any eventual output of an Infinite Time Turing machine (halting or otherwise); using this the Infinite Time Turing Degrees are considered, and it is shown how the jump operator coincides with the production of mastercodes for the constructible hierarchy; further that (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  12.  26
    Differences between Resource Bounded Degree Structures.Theodore A. Slaman & Michael~E. Mytilinaios - 2003 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 44 (1):1-12.
    We exhibit a structural difference between the truth-table degrees of the sets which are truth-table above 0′ and the PTIME-Turing degrees of all sets. Though the structures do not have the same isomorphism type, demonstrating this fact relies on developing their common theory.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13. Eventually Infinite Time Turing Machine Degrees: Infinite Time Decidable Reals.P. D. Welch - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (3):1193-1203.
    We characterise explicitly the decidable predicates on integers of Infinite Time Turing machines, in terms of admissibility theory and the constructible hierarchy. We do this by pinning down $\zeta$, the least ordinal not the length of any eventual output of an Infinite Time Turing machine ; using this the Infinite Time Turing Degrees are considered, and it is shown how the jump operator coincides with the production of mastercodes for the constructible hierarchy; further that the natural (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14. An Exact Pair for the Arithmetic Degrees Whose Join is Not a Weak Uniform Upper Bound.Harold T. Hodes - 1982 - Recursive Function Theory-Newsletters 28.
    Proof uses forcing on perfect trees for 2-quantifier sentences in the language of arithmetic. The result extends to exact pairs for the hyperarithmetic degrees.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Differences between Resource Bounded Degree Structures.Michael E. Mytilinaios & Theodore A. Slaman - 2003 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 44 (1):1-12.
    We exhibit a structural difference between the truth-table degrees of the sets which are truth-table above 0′ and the PTIME-Turing degrees of all sets. Though the structures do not have the same isomorphism type, demonstrating this fact relies on developing their common theory.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  53
    Bounding non- GL ₂ and R.E.A.Klaus Ambos-Spies, Decheng Ding, Wei Wang & Liang Yu - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (3):989-1000.
    We prove that every Turing degree a bounding some non-GL₂ degree is recursively enumerable in and above (r.e.a.) some 1-generic degree.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  17.  47
    Bounding Homogeneous Models.Barbara F. Csima, Valentina S. Harizanov, Denis R. Hirschfeldt & Robert I. Soare - 2007 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 72 (1):305 - 323.
    A Turing degree d is homogeneous bounding if every complete decidable (CD) theory has a d-decidable homogeneous model A, i.e., the elementary diagram De (A) has degree d. It follows from results of Macintyre and Marker that every PA degree (i.e., every degree of a complete extension of Peano Arithmetic) is homogeneous bounding. We prove that in fact a degree is homogeneous bounding if and only if it is a PA degree. We do this by showing that there is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  13
    The ibT degrees of computably enumerable sets are not dense.George Barmpalias & Andrew E. M. Lewis - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 141 (1-2):51-60.
    We show that the identity bounded Turing degrees of computably enumerable sets are not dense.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  19.  39
    The computable Lipschitz degrees of computably enumerable sets are not dense.Adam R. Day - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (12):1588-1602.
    The computable Lipschitz reducibility was introduced by Downey, Hirschfeldt and LaForte under the name of strong weak truth-table reducibility [6]). This reducibility measures both the relative randomness and the relative computational power of real numbers. This paper proves that the computable Lipschitz degrees of computably enumerable sets are not dense. An immediate corollary is that the Solovay degrees of strongly c.e. reals are not dense. There are similarities to Barmpalias and Lewis’ proof that the identity bounded (...) degrees of c.e. sets are not dense [2]), however the problem for the computable Lipschitz degrees is more complex. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20.  55
    Low upper bounds of ideals.Antonín Kučera & Theodore A. Slaman - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (2):517-534.
    We show that there is a low T-upper bound for the class of K-trivial sets, namely those which are weak from the point of view of algorithmic randomness. This result is a special case of a more general characterization of ideals in $\Delta _2^0 $ T-degrees for which there is a low T-upper bound.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  21.  28
    The degree spectra of homogeneous models.Karen Lange - 2008 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 73 (3):1009-1028.
    Much previous study has been done on the degree spectra of prime models of a complete atomic decidable theory. Here we study the analogous questions for homogeneous models. We say a countable model A has a d-basis if the types realized in A are all computable and the Turing degree d can list $\Delta _{0}^{0}$ -indices for all types realized in A. We say A has a d-decidable copy if there exists a model B ≅ A such that the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  34
    Direct and local definitions of the Turing jump.Richard A. Shore - 2007 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 7 (2):229-262.
    We show that there are Π5 formulas in the language of the Turing degrees, [Formula: see text], with ≤, ∨ and ∧, that define the relations x″ ≤ y″, x″ = y″ and so {x ∈ L2 = x ≥ y|x″ = y″} in any jump ideal containing 0. There are also Σ6&Π6 and Π8 formulas that define the relations w = x″ and w = x', respectively, in any such ideal [Formula: see text]. In the language with (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  23.  18
    The partial orderings of the computably enumerable ibT-degrees and cl-degrees are not elementarily equivalent.Klaus Ambos-Spies, Philipp Bodewig, Yun Fan & Thorsten Kräling - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (5):577-588.
    We show that, in the partial ordering of the computably enumerable computable Lipschitz degrees, there is a degree a>0a>0 such that the class of the degrees which do not cup to a is not bounded by any degree less than a. Since Ambos-Spies [1] has shown that, in the partial ordering of the c.e. identity-bounded Turing degrees, for any degree a>0a>0 the degrees which do not cup to a are bounded by the (...))
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  23
    Randomness, Lowness and Degrees.George Barmpalias, Andrew E. M. Lewis & Mariya Soskova - 2008 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 73 (2):559 - 577.
    We say that A ≤LR B if every B-random number is A-random. Intuitively this means that if oracle A can identify some patterns on some real γ. In other words. B is at least as good as A for this purpose. We study the structure of the LR degrees globally and locally (i.e., restricted to the computably enumberable degrees) and their relationship with the Turing degrees. Among other results we show that whenever α in not GL₂ (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  25.  3
    On reals with -bounded complexity and compressive power.Ian Herbert - 2016 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 81 (3):833-855.
    The Kolmogorov complexity of a finite binary string is the length of the shortest description of the string. This gives rise to some ‘standard’ lowness notions for reals: A isK-trivial if its initial segments have the lowest possible complexity and A is low forKif using A as an oracle does not decrease the complexity of strings by more than a constant factor. We weaken these notions by requiring the defining inequalities to hold only up to all${\rm{\Delta }}_2^0$orders, and call the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  45
    Hypersimplicity and semicomputability in the weak truth table degrees.George Barmpalias - 2005 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 44 (8):1045-1065.
    We study the classes of hypersimple and semicomputable sets as well as their intersection in the weak truth table degrees. We construct degrees that are not bounded by hypersimple degrees outside any non-trivial upper cone of Turing degrees and show that the hypersimple-free c.e. wtt degrees are downwards dense in the c.e. wtt degrees. We also show that there is no maximal (w.r.t. ≤wtt) hypersimple wtt degree. Moreover, we consider the sets that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27.  13
    Effective Domination and the Bounded Jump.Keng Meng Ng & Hongyuan Yu - 2020 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 61 (2):203-225.
    We study the relationship between effective domination properties and the bounded jump. We answer two open questions about the bounded jump: We prove that the analogue of Sacks jump inversion fails for the bounded jump and the wtt-reducibility. We prove that no c.e. bounded high set can be low by showing that they all have to be Turing complete. We characterize the class of c.e. bounded high sets as being those sets computing the Halting (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  12
    Classes bounded by incomplete sets.Kejia Ho & Frank Stephan - 2002 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 116 (1-3):273-295.
    We study connections between strong reducibilities and properties of computably enumerable sets such as simplicity. We say that a class of computably enumerable sets bounded iff there is an m-incomplete computably enumerable set A such that every set in is m-reducible to A. For example, we show that the class of effectively simple sets is bounded; but the class of maximal sets is not. Furthermore, the class of computably enumerable sets Turing reducible to a computably enumerable set (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  28
    A jump operator on honest subrecursive degrees.Lars Kristiansen - 1998 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 37 (2):105-125.
    It is well known that the structure of honest elementary degrees is a lattice with rather strong density properties. Let $\mbox{\bf a} \cup \mbox{\bf b}$ and $\mbox{\bf a} \cap \mbox{\bf b}$ denote respectively the join and the meet of the degrees $\mbox{\bf a}$ and $\mbox{\bf b}$ . This paper introduces a jump operator ( $\cdot'$ ) on the honest elementary degrees and defines canonical degrees $\mbox{\bf 0},\mbox{\bf 0}', \mbox{\bf 0}^{\prime \prime },\ldots$ and low and high (...) analogous to the corresponding concepts for the Turing degrees. Among others, the following results about the structure of the honest elementary degrees are shown: There exist low degrees, and there exist degrees which are neither low nor high. Every degree above $\mbox{\bf 0}'$ is the jump of some degree, moreover, for every degree $\mbox{\bf c}$ above $\mbox{\bf 0}'$ there exist degrees $\mbox{\bf a},\mbox{\bf b}$ such that $\mbox{\bf c}=\mbox{\bf a} \cup \mbox{\bf b} = \mbox{{\bf a}}'=\mbox{\bf b}'$ . We have $\mbox{\bf a}'\cup \mbox{\bf b}' \leq (\mbox{\bf a}\cup\mbox{\bf b})'$ and $\mbox{\bf a}'\cap \mbox{\bf b}' \geq (\mbox{\bf a}\cap \mbox{\bf b})'$ . The jump operator is of course monotonic, i.e. $\mbox{\bf a}\leq\mbox{{\bf b}}\Rightarrow \mbox{\bf a}'\leq \mbox{\bf b}'$ . We prove that every situation compatible with $\mbox{\bf a}\leq\mbox{\bf b}\Rightarrow \mbox{\bf a}'\leq \mbox{\bf b}'$ is realized in the structure, e.g. we have incomparable degrees $\mbox{\bf a},\mbox{\bf b}$ such that $\mbox{\bf a}'<\mbox{\bf b}'$ and incomparable degrees $\mbox{\bf a},\mbox{\bf b}$ such that $\mbox{\bf a}' = \mbox{\bf b}'$ etcetera. We are able to prove all these results without the traditional recursion theoretic constructions. Our proof method relies on the fact that the growth of the functions in a degree is bounded. This technique also yields a very simple proof of an old result, namely that the structure is a lattice. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  30.  16
    Muchnik degrees and cardinal characteristics.Benoit Monin & André Nies - 2021 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 86 (2):471-498.
    A mass problem is a set of functions $\omega \to \omega $. For mass problems ${\mathcal {C}}, {\mathcal {D}}$, one says that ${\mathcal {C}}$ is Muchnik reducible to ${\mathcal {D}}$ if each function in ${\mathcal {C}}$ is computed by a function in ${\mathcal {D}}$. In this paper we study some highness properties of Turing oracles, which we view as mass problems. We compare them with respect to Muchnik reducibility and its uniform strengthening, Medvedev reducibility.For $p \in [0,1]$ let ${\mathcal (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  25
    Jumping to a Uniform Upper Bound.Harold T. Hodes - 1982 - Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society 85 (4):600-602.
    A uniform upper bound on a class of Turing degrees is the Turing degree of a function which parametrizes the collection of all functions whose degree is in the given class. I prove that if a is a uniform upper bound on an ideal of degrees then a is the jump of a degree c with this additional property: there is a uniform bound b<a so that b V c < a.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  16
    Post's Problem for Reducibilities of Bounded Complexity.Valeriy K. Bulitko - 2002 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 48 (3):367-373.
    In this paper we consider the we known method by E. Post of solving the problem of construction of recursively enumerable sets that have a degree intermediate between the degrees of recursive and complete sets with respect to a given reducibility. Post considered reducibilities ≤m, ≤btt, ≤tt and ≤T and solved the problem for al of them except ≤T. Here we extend Post's original method of construction of incomplete sets onto two wide classes of sub-Turing reducibilities what were (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  8
    On New Notions of Algorithmic Dimension, Immunity, and Medvedev Degree.David J. Webb - 2022 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 28 (4):532-533.
    We prove various results connected together by the common thread of computability theory.First, we investigate a new notion of algorithmic dimension, the inescapable dimension, which lies between the effective Hausdorff and packing dimensions. We also study its generalizations, obtaining an embedding of the Turing degrees into notions of dimension.We then investigate a new notion of computability theoretic immunity that arose in the course of the previous study, that of a set of natural numbers with no co-enumerable subsets. We (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  14
    The existence of high nonbounding degrees in the difference hierarchy.Chi Tat Chong, Angsheng Li & Yue Yang - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 138 (1):31-51.
    We study the jump hierarchy of d.c.e. Turing degrees and show that there exists a high d.c.e. degree d which does not bound any minimal pair of d.c.e. degrees.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  81
    On the structures inside truth-table degrees.Frank Stephan - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (2):731-770.
    The following theorems on the structure inside nonrecursive truth-table degrees are established: Dëgtev's result that the number of bounded truth-table degrees inside a truth-table degree is at least two is improved by showing that this number is infinite. There are even infinite chains and antichains of bounded truth-table degrees inside every truth-table degree. The latter implies an affirmative answer to the following question of Jockusch: does every truth-table degree contain an infinite antichain of many-one (...)? Some but not all truth-table degrees have a least bounded truth-table degree. The technique to construct such a degree is used to solve an open problem of Beigel, Gasarch and Owings: there are Turing degrees (constructed as hyperimmune-free truth-table degrees) which consist only of 2-subjective sets and therefore do not contain any objective set. Furthermore, a truth-table degree consisting of three positive degrees is constructed where one positive degree consists of enumerable semirecursive sets, one of coenumerable semirecursive sets and one of sets, which are neither enumerable nor coenumerable nor semirecursive. So Jockusch's result that there are at least three positive degrees inside a truth-table degree is optimal. The number of positive degrees inside a truth-table degree can also be some other odd integer as for example nineteen, but it is never an even finite number. (shrink)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  51
    The Sacks density theorem and Σ2-bounding.Marcia J. Groszek, Michael E. Mytilinaios & Theodore A. Slaman - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (2):450 - 467.
    The Sacks Density Theorem [7] states that the Turing degrees of the recursively enumerable sets are dense. We show that the Density Theorem holds in every model of P - + BΣ 2 . The proof has two components: a lemma that in any model of P - + BΣ 2 , if B is recursively enumerable and incomplete then IΣ 1 holds relative to B and an adaptation of Shore's [9] blocking technique in α-recursion theory to models (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  37.  30
    Characterizing the Join-Irreducible Medvedev Degrees.Paul Shafer - 2011 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 52 (1):21-38.
    We characterize the join-irreducible Medvedev degrees as the degrees of complements of Turing ideals, thereby solving a problem posed by Sorbi. We use this characterization to prove that there are Medvedev degrees above the second-least degree that do not bound any join-irreducible degrees above this second-least degree. This solves a problem posed by Sorbi and Terwijn. Finally, we prove that the filter generated by the degrees of closed sets is not prime. This solves a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  38.  23
    On Turing degrees of points in computable topology.Iraj Kalantari & Larry Welch - 2008 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 54 (5):470-482.
    This paper continues our study of computable point-free topological spaces and the metamathematical points in them. For us, a point is the intersection of a sequence of basic open sets with compact and nested closures. We call such a sequence a sharp filter. A function fF from points to points is generated by a function F from basic open sets to basic open sets such that sharp filters map to sharp filters. We restrict our study to functions that have at (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  47
    Turing degrees of certain isomorphic images of computable relations.Valentina S. Harizanov - 1998 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 93 (1-3):103-113.
    A model is computable if its domain is a computable set and its relations and functions are uniformly computable. Let be a computable model and let R be an extra relation on the domain of . That is, R is not named in the language of . We define to be the set of Turing degrees of the images f under all isomorphisms f from to computable models. We investigate conditions on and R which are sufficient and necessary (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  40.  15
    The Turing Degrees and Keisler’s Order.Maryanthe Malliaris & Saharon Shelah - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (1):331-341.
    There is a Turing functional $\Phi $ taking $A^\prime $ to a theory $T_A$ whose complexity is exactly that of the jump of A, and which has the property that $A \leq _T B$ if and only if $T_A \trianglelefteq T_B$ in Keisler’s order. In fact, by more elaborate means and related theories, we may keep the complexity at the level of A without using the jump.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  15
    Turing degrees in Polish spaces and decomposability of Borel functions.Vassilios Gregoriades, Takayuki Kihara & Keng Meng Ng - 2020 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 21 (1):2050021.
    We give a partial answer to an important open problem in descriptive set theory, the Decomposability Conjecture for Borel functions on an analytic subset of a Polish space to a separable metrizable space. Our techniques employ deep results from effective descriptive set theory and recursion theory. In fact it is essential to extend several prominent results in recursion theory (e.g. the Shore-Slaman Join Theorem) to the setting of Polish spaces. As a by-product we give both positive and negative results on (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  9
    Turing degrees and randomness for continuous measures.Mingyang Li & Jan Reimann - 2024 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 63 (1):39-59.
    We study degree-theoretic properties of reals that are not random with respect to any continuous probability measure (NCR). To this end, we introduce a family of generalized Hausdorff measures based on the iterates of the “dissipation” function of a continuous measure and study the effective nullsets given by the corresponding Solovay tests. We introduce two constructions that preserve non-randomness with respect to a given continuous measure. This enables us to prove the existence of NCR reals in a number of (...) degrees. In particular, we show that every \(\Delta ^0_2\) -degree contains an NCR element. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  29
    Turing degrees and many-one degrees of maximal sets.Manuel Lerman - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (1):29-40.
    Martin [4, Theorems 1 and 2] proved that a Turing degree a is the degree of a maximal set if, and only if, a′ = 0″. Lachlan has shown that maximal sets have minimal many-one degrees [2, §1] and that every nonrecursive r.e. Turing degree contains a minimal many-one degree [2, Theorem 4]. Our aim here is to show that any r.e. Turing degree a of a maximal set contains an infinite number of maximal sets whose (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  20
    Turing degree spectra of differentially closed fields.David Marker & Russell Miller - 2017 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 82 (1):1-25.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  26
    Turing degrees of hypersimple relations on computable structures.Valentina S. Harizanov - 2003 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 121 (2-3):209-226.
    Let be an infinite computable structure, and let R be an additional computable relation on its domain A. The syntactic notion of formal hypersimplicity of R on , first introduced and studied by Hird, is analogous to the computability-theoretic notion of hypersimplicity of R on A, given the definability of certain effective sequences of relations on A. Assuming that R is formally hypersimple on , we give general sufficient conditions for the existence of a computable isomorphic copy of on whose (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  23
    The Turing degrees below generics and randoms.Richard A. Shore - 2014 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 79 (1):171-178.
    If X0and X1are both generic, the theories of the degrees below X0and X1are the same. The same is true if both are random. We show that then-genericity orn-randomness of X do not suffice to guarantee that the degrees below X have these common theories. We also show that these two theories are different. These results answer questions of Jockusch as well as Barmpalias, Day and Lewis.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  19
    The possible turing degree of the nonzero member in a two element degree spectrum.Valentina S. Harizanov - 1993 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 60 (1):1-30.
    We construct a recursive model , a recursive subset R of its domain, and a Turing degree x 0 satisfying the following condition. The nonrecursive images of R under all isomorphisms from to other recursive models are of Turing degree x and cannot be recursively enumerable.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  48.  11
    Bounding cappable degrees.Angsheng Li - 2000 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 39 (5):311-352.
    It will be shown that there exist computably enumerable degrees a and b such that a $>$ b, and for any computably enumerable degree u, if u $\leq$ a and u is cappable, then u $<$ b.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  46
    Bounding minimal degrees by computably enumerable degrees.Angsheng Li & Dongping Yang - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (4):1319-1347.
    In this paper, we prove that there exist computably enumerable degrees a and b such that $\mathbf{a} > \mathbf{b}$ and for any degree x, if x ≤ a and x is a minimal degree, then $\mathbf{x}.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  50
    Maximal pairs of c.e. reals in the computably Lipschitz degrees.Yun Fan & Liang Yu - 2011 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (5):357-366.
    Computably Lipschitz reducibility , was suggested as a measure of relative randomness. We say α≤clβ if α is Turing reducible to β with oracle use on x bounded by x+c. In this paper, we prove that for any non-computable real, there exists a c.e. real so that no c.e. real can cl-compute both of them. So every non-computable c.e. real is the half of a cl-maximal pair of c.e. reals.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 1000