Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. How Galileo dropped the ball and Fermat picked it up.Bryan W. Roberts - 2011 - Synthese 180 (3):337-356.
    This paper introduces a little-known episode in the history of physics, in which a mathematical proof by Pierre Fermat vindicated Galileo’s characterization of freefall. The first part of the paper reviews the historical context leading up to Fermat’s proof. The second part illustrates how a physical and a mathematical insight enabled Fermat’s result, and that a simple modification would satisfy any of Fermat’s critics. The result is an illustration of how a purely theoretical argument can settle an apparently empirical debate.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Radical mathematical Thomism: beings of reason and divine decrees in Torricelli’s philosophy of mathematics.Paolo Palmieri - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 40 (2):131-142.
    Evangelista Torricelli is perhaps best known for being the most gifted of Galileo’s pupils, and for his works based on indivisibles, especially his stunning cubature of an infinite hyperboloid. Scattered among Torricelli’s writings, we find numerous traces of the philosophy of mathematics underlying his mathematical practice. Though virtually neglected by historians and philosophers alike, these traces reveal that Torricelli’s mathematical practice was informed by an original philosophy of mathematics. The latter was dashed with strains of Thomistic metaphysics and theology. Torricelli’s (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Dome: An Unexpectedly Simple Failure of Determinism.John D. Norton - 2008 - Philosophy of Science 75 (5):786-798.
    Newton’s equations of motion tell us that a mass at rest at the apex of a dome with the shape specified here can spontaneously move. It has been suggested that this indeterminism should be discounted since it draws on an incomplete rendering of Newtonian physics, or it is “unphysical,” or it employs illicit idealizations. I analyze and reject each of these reasons. †To contact the author, please write to: Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, PA (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Notes & Correspondence.A. Hall, I. Cohen, Stillman Drake, Denis Duveen & Herbert Klickstein - 1958 - Isis 49:342-349.
  • Notes & Correspondence.A. R. Hall, Stillman Drake, Denis I. Duveen & Herbert S. Klickstein - 1958 - Isis 49 (3):342-349.
  • Gassendi and l'Affaire Galilée of the Laws of Motion.Paolo Galluzzi - 2001 - Science in Context 14 (s1):239-275.
    In the lively discussions on Galileo's laws of motion after the Pisan's death, we observe what might be called a new “Galilean affair.” That is, a trial brought against his new science of motion mainly by French and Italian Jesuits with the substantial adherence of M. Mersenne. This new trail was originated by Gassendi's presentation of Galileo's de motu not simply as a perfectly coherent doctrine, but also as a convincing argument in favor of the truth of Copernicanism.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Gassendi and l'Affaire Galilée of the Laws of Motion.Paolo Galluzzi - 2000 - Science in Context 13 (3-4):509-545.
    In the lively discussions on Galileo's laws of motion after the Pisan's death, we observe what might be called a new “Galilean affair.” That is, a trial brought against his new science of motion mainly by French and Italian Jesuits with the substantial adherence of M. Mersenne. This new trail was originated by Gassendi's presentation of Galileo's de motu not simply as a perfectly coherent doctrine, but also as a convincing argument in favor of the truth of Copernicanism.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Uniform Acceleration, Space, and Time.Stillman Drake - 1970 - British Journal for the History of Science 5 (1):21-43.
    The most reliable source for a reconstruction of Galileo's progress toward a science of motion is the series of undated fragmentary notes on that subject preserved in Codex A of the Galilean manuscripts at Florence. A gathering of such fragments was published by Favaro in the National Edition of Galileo's works, following the Discorsi. The more sophisticated fragments are clearly associated with the composition of that work, and show a definite and consistent understanding of acceleration. Eliminating those, it will be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Galileo's 1604 Fragment on Falling Bodies.Stillman Drake - 1969 - British Journal for the History of Science 4 (4):340-358.
    The first attempted derivation by Galileo of the law relating space and time in free fall that has survived is preserved on an otherwise unidentified sheet bound among his manuscripts preserved at Florence. It is undoubtedly closely associated with a letter from Galileo to Paolo Sarpi, dated 16 October 1604, which somehow found its way into the Seminary of Pisa, where it is still preserved. Those two documents, together with the letter from Sarpi to Galileo which seems to have inspired (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Galileo's Rejection of the Possibility of Velocity Changing Uniformly with Respect to Distance.I. Cohen - 1956 - Isis 47:231-235.
  • Galileo's Rejection of the Possibility of Velocity Changing Uniformly with Respect to Distance.I. Bernard Cohen - 1956 - Isis 47 (3):231-235.
  • Dialogues Concerning Two New Sciences.Galileo Galilei - 1914 - Dover Publications.
    FIRST DAY INTERLOCUTORS: SALVIATI, SA- GREDO AND SIMPLICIO ALV. The constant activity which you Venetians display in your famous arsenal suggests to the ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations