The Paradox of Liberal Politics in the South African Context: Alfred Hoernlé's Critique of Liberalism's Pact with White Domination

Critical Philosophy of Race 4 (2):163-181 (2016)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

This article traces the evolution by which in the context of 1930s South Africa the liberal philosopher Alfred Hoernlé came to recognize the inability of classical liberalism to address the problems of a society in which a racial hierarchy had become deeply entrenched. Although he must be criticized for his patriarchal approach and for the pessimism that led him to take White attitudes toward Black South Africans as an unchangeable part of the situation that simply had to be accepted, his insight into the limits of liberalism still resonates. While most White commentators were still thinking of racism in terms of beliefs and attitudes, he already understood that the problem lay in the systemic adoption of “techniques of domination” or what we today might call institutional racism. Although his proposal in 1939 that “Total Separation” was “a legitimate application of sound liberal ideas” was deeply problematic in context and might well have had a serious negative impact, it should be understood that it was intended to highlight the fundamental paradox into which liberalism fell when attempting to solve the problems it had helped to create by its belief in a civilizing mission that began with violence.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,853

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

R.F.A. Hoernlé and Idealist Liberalism in South Africa1.W. Sweet - 2010 - South African Journal of Philosophy 29 (2):178-194.
Republican freedom and the rule of law.Christian List - 2006 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 5 (2):201-220.
What to Make of the Liberal Paradox?Mathias Risse - 2001 - Theory and Decision 50 (2):169-196.
A Communitarian Critique of Liberalism.Daniel A. Bell - 2005 - Analyse & Kritik 27 (2):215-238.
The Politics of Virtue: Post-Liberalism and the Human Future.John Milbank & Adrian Pabst - 2015 - New York: Rowman & Littlefield International. Edited by Adrian Pabst.
When a "white horse" is not a "horse".Kirill Ole Thompson - 1995 - Philosophy East and West 45 (4):481-499.
Politics of the ego: Stirner's critique of liberalism.Saul Newman - 2002 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 5 (3):1-26.
Political or Moral?An-kui Tan - 2007 - Modern Philosophy 5:99-104.
Liberal perspectives for South Asia.Rajiva Wijesinha (ed.) - 2009 - New Delhi: Cambridge University Press India under the imprint of Foundation Books.
Shklar's Legalism and the Liberal Paradox.Tiphaine Dickson - 2015 - Constellations 22 (2):188-198.
Jacob Talmon between Zionism and Cold War Liberalism.Malachi H. Hacohen - 2008 - History of European Ideas 34 (2):146-157.
Privilege or recognition? The myth of state neutrality.Tim Nieguth - 1999 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 2 (2):112-131.

Analytics

Added to PP
2022-04-08

Downloads
7 (#1,387,044)

6 months
3 (#976,504)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Robert Bernasconi
Pennsylvania State University

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

The Open Society and its Enemies.Karl R. Popper - 1952 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 142:629-634.
R.F.A. Hoernlé and Idealist Liberalism in South Africa1.W. Sweet - 2010 - South African Journal of Philosophy 29 (2):178-194.
V.—critical notices.R. F. Alfred Hoernle - 1941 - Mind 50 (200):393-401.

View all 9 references / Add more references