Thought structure, belief content, and possession conditions

Acta Analytica 23 (3):207-231 (2008)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

According to Peacocke, concepts are individuated by their possession conditions, which are specified in terms of conditions in which certain propositions containing those concepts are believed. In support, Peacocke tries to explain what it is for a thought to have a structure and what it is for a belief to have a propositional content. I show that the possession condition theory cannot answer such fundamental questions. Peacocke’s theory founders because concepts are metaphysically fundamental. They individuate the propositions and thoughts containing them, which in turn individuate the propositional attitudes that are relations to those propositions or thoughts.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,435

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

How to use a concept you reject.Mark McCullagh - 2011 - Philosophical Quarterly 61 (243):293-319.
Concepts and epistemic individuation.Wayne A. Davis - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (2):290-325.
The Emperor’s New Concepts.Neil Tennant - 2002 - Noûs 36 (s16):345-377.
Introduction.Neil Tennant - 2008 - Philosophia Mathematica 16 (1):1-3.
Bookreviews.B. C. Postow - 1988 - Annals of Science 45 (6):175-178.
Can possession conditions individuate concepts? [REVIEW]Christopher Peacocke - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (2):433-460.
Twin-earth externalism and concept possession.Derek Ball - 2007 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 85 (3):457-472.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
119 (#149,073)

6 months
3 (#981,909)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Wayne Davis
Georgetown University

Citations of this work

Propositions as Structured Cognitive Event‐Types.Wayne A. Davis - 2021 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 102 (3):665-692.

Add more citations