Results for 'Plane geometry'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  14
    Plane geometry theorem proving using forward chaining.Arthur J. Nevins - 1975 - Artificial Intelligence 6 (1):1-23.
  2.  22
    Plane Geometry in Spacetime.N. David Mermin - 2009 - In Wayne C. Myrvold & Joy Christian (eds.), Quantum Reality, Relativistic Causality, and Closing the Epistemic Circle. Springer. pp. 327--347.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. The twofold role of diagrams in Euclid’s plane geometry.Marco Panza - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):55-102.
    Proposition I.1 is, by far, the most popular example used to justify the thesis that many of Euclid’s geometric arguments are diagram-based. Many scholars have recently articulated this thesis in different ways and argued for it. My purpose is to reformulate it in a quite general way, by describing what I take to be the twofold role that diagrams play in Euclid’s plane geometry (EPG). Euclid’s arguments are object-dependent. They are about geometric objects. Hence, they cannot be diagram-based (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  4.  26
    Groups and Plane Geometry.Victor Pambuccian - 2005 - Studia Logica 81 (3):387-398.
    We show that the first-order theory of a large class of plane geometries and the first-order theory of their groups of motions, understood both as groups with a unary predicate singling out line-reflections, and as groups acting on sets, are mutually inter-pretable.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5.  29
    A Proposition of Elementary Plane Geometry that Implies the Continuum Hypothesis.Frederick Bagemihl - 1961 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 7 (1-5):77-79.
  6.  29
    Ternary operations as primitive notions for plane geometry II.Victor Pambuccian - 1992 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 38 (1):345-348.
    We proved in the first part [1] that plane geometry over Pythagorean fields is axiomatizable by quantifier-free axioms in a language with three individual constants, one binary and three ternary operation symbols. In this paper we prove that two of these operation symbols are superfluous.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  12
    Enthymemathical proofs and canonical proofs in Euclid's plane geometry.Abel Lassalle & Marco Panza - 2018 - In Claudio Bartocci (ed.), The Philosophers and Mathematics. Springer Verlag. pp. 127-144.
    Since the application of Postulate I.2 in Euclid's Elements is not uniform, one could wonder in what way should it be applied in Euclid's plane geometry. Besides legitimizing questions like this from the perspective of a philosophy of mathematical practice, we sketch a general perspective of conceptual analysis of mathematical texts, which involves an extended notion of mathematical theory as system of authorizations, and an audience-dependent notion of proof.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  21
    Ternary Operations as Primitive Notions for Constructive Plane Geometry IV.Victor Pambuccian - 1994 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 40 (1):76-86.
    In this paper we provide a quantifier-free constructive axiomatization for Euclidean planes in a first-order language with only ternary operation symbols and three constant symbols . We also determine the algorithmic theories of some ‘naturally occurring’ plane geometries.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  26
    A common axiom set for classical and intuitionistic plane geometry.Melinda Lombard & Richard Vesley - 1998 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 95 (1-3):229-255.
    We describe a first order axiom set which yields the classical first order Euclidean geometry of Tarski when used with classical logic, and yields an intuitionistic Euclidean geometry when used with intuitionistic logic. The first order language has a single six place atomic predicate and no function symbols. The intuitionistic system has a computational interpretation in recursive function theory, that is, a realizability interpretation analogous to those given by Kleene for intuitionistic arithmetic and analysis. This interpretation shows the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  10.  16
    Ternary operations as primitive notions for constructive plane geometry III.Victor Pambuccian - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):393-402.
    This paper continues the investigations begun in [6] and continued in [7] about quantifier-free axiomatizations of plane Euclidean geometry using ternary operations. We show that plane Euclidean geometry over Archimedean ordered Euclidean fields can be axiomatized using only two ternary operations if one allows axioms that are not first-order but universal Lw1,w sentences. The operations are: the transport of a segment on a halfline that starts at one of the endpoints of the given segment, and the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  9
    Ternary Operations as Primitive Notions for Constructive Plane Geometry V.Victor Pambuccian - 1994 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 40 (4):455-477.
    In this paper we provide a quantifier-free, constructive axiomatization of metric-Euclidean and of rectangular planes . The languages in which the axiom systems are expressed contain three individual constants and two ternary operations. We also provide an axiom system in algorithmic logic for finite Euclidean planes, and for several minimal metric-Euclidean planes. The axiom systems proposed will be used in a sequel to this paper to provide ‘the simplest possible’ axiom systems for several fragments of plane Euclidean geometry.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12.  22
    Ternary Operations as Primitive Notions for Constructive Plane Geometry VI.Victor Pambuccian - 1995 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 41 (3):384-394.
    In this paper we provide quantifier-free, constructive axiomatizations for several fragments of plane Euclidean geometry over Euclidean fields, such that each axiom contains at most 4 variables. The languages in which they are expressed contain only at most ternary operations. In some precisely defined sense these axiomatizations are the simplest possible.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  8
    Enthymemathical Proofs and Canonical Proofs in Euclid’s Plane Geometry.Marco Panza & Abel Lassalle-Casanave - 2018 - In Hassan Tahiri (ed.), The Philosophers and Mathematics: Festschrift for Roshdi Rashed. Cham: Springer Verlag. pp. 127-144.
    Since the application of Postulate I.2 in Euclid’s Elements is not uniform, one could wonder in what way should it be applied in Euclid’s plane geometry. Besides legitimizing questions like this from the perspective of a philosophy of mathematical practice, we sketch a general perspective of conceptual analysis of mathematical texts, which involves an extended notion of mathematical theory as system of authorizations, and an audience-dependent notion of proof.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Corrections to “Ternary operations as primitive notions for constructive plane geometry III, V, VI”.V. Pambuccian - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47:136.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Quantifier-free axioms for constructive affine plane geometry.Patrick Suppes - 2000 - Synthese 125 (1-2):263-281.
  16.  20
    Equivalence to the Continuum Hypothesis of a Certain Proposition of Elementary Plane Geometry.Roy O. Davies - 1962 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 8 (2):109-111.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  24
    Equivalence to the Continuum Hypothesis of a Certain Proposition of Elementary Plane Geometry.Roy O. Davies - 1962 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 8 (2):109-111.
  18.  14
    A structural and foundational analysis of euclid’s plane geometry: The case study of continuity.Pierluigi Graziani - 2014 - In Vincenzo Fano, Francesco Orilia & Giovanni Macchia (eds.), Space and Time: A Priori and a Posteriori Studies. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 63-106.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  37
    Ternary Operations as Primitive Notions for Constructive Plane Geometry.Victor Pambuccian - 1989 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 35 (6):531-535.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  35
    Ternary operations as primitive notions for plane geometry II.Victor Pambuccian - 1992 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 38 (1):345-348.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  8
    Review: H. L. Royden, Remarks on Primitive Notions for Elementary Euclidean and Non-Euclidean Plane Geometry[REVIEW]Leslaw W. Szczerba - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (3):473-474.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  35
    Royden H. L.. Remarks on primitive notions for elementary Euclidean and non-Euclidean plane geometry. The axiomatic method with special reference to geometry and physics, Proceedings of an International Symposium held at the University of California, Berkeley, December 26,1957-January 4, 1958, Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam 1959, pp. 86–96. [REVIEW]Lesław W. Szczerba - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (3):473-474.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  34
    Max Beberman and Herbert E. Vaughan. High school mathematics. Course 2. Plane geometry with appendices on logic and solid geometry. D. C. Heath and Company, Boston, Englewood, Chicago, San Francisco, Atlanta, Dallas, London, and Toronto, 1965, xi + 584 pp. - Max Beberman and Herbert E. Vaughan. High school mathematics. Course 2. Plane geometry with appendices on logic and solid geometry. Teacher's edition. D. C. Heath and Company, Boston, Englewood, Chicago, San Francisco, Atlanta, Dallas, London, and Toronto, 1965, 608 pp. [REVIEW]Theodore Hailperin - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (4):672-673.
  24. On the relationship between plane and solid geometry.Andrew Arana & Paolo Mancosu - 2012 - Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (2):294-353.
    Traditional geometry concerns itself with planimetric and stereometric considerations, which are at the root of the division between plane and solid geometry. To raise the issue of the relation between these two areas brings with it a host of different problems that pertain to mathematical practice, epistemology, semantics, ontology, methodology, and logic. In addition, issues of psychology and pedagogy are also important here. To our knowledge there is no single contribution that studies in detail even one of (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  25. New Plane and Solid Geometry.Wooster Woodruff Beman - 1900 - The Monist 10:473.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  28
    Axes, planes and tubes, or the geometry of embryogenesis.Sabine Brauckmann - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (4):381-390.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  18
    The complexity of plane hyperbolic incidence geometry is∀∃∀∃.Victor Pambuccian - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (3):277-281.
    We show that plane hyperbolic geometry, expressed in terms of points and the ternary relation of collinearity alone, cannot be expressed by means of axioms of complexity at most ∀∃∀, but that there is an axiom system, all of whose axioms are ∀∃∀∃ sentences. This remains true for Klingenberg's generalized hyperbolic planes, with arbitrary ordered fields as coordinate fields.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  28. ew Plane and Solid Geometry[REVIEW]Wooster Woodruff Beman - 1900 - Ancient Philosophy (Misc) 10:473.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  26
    Constructive Axiomatization of Plane Hyperbolic Geometry.Victor Pambuccian - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (4):475-488.
    We provide a universal axiom system for plane hyperbolic geometry in a firstorder language with two sorts of individual variables, ‘points’ and ‘lines’ , containing three individual constants, A0, A1, A2, standing for three non-collinear points, two binary operation symbols, φ and ι, with φ = l to be interpreted as ‘[MATHEMATICAL SCRIPT SMALL L] is the line joining A and B’ , and ι = P to be interpreted as [MATHEMATICAL SCRIPT SMALL L]P is the point of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  23
    Point-free geometry, ovals, and half-planes.Giangiacomo Gerla & Rafał Gruszczyński - 2017 - Review of Symbolic Logic 10 (2):237-258.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  23
    Constructive Axiomatizations of Plane Absolute, Euclidean and Hyperbolic Geometry.Victor Pambuccian - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (1):129-136.
    In this paper we provide quantifier-free, constructive axiomatizations for 2-dimensional absolute, Euclidean, and hyperbolic geometry. The main novelty consists in the first-order languages in which the axiom systems are formulated.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32.  29
    The Simplest Axiom System for Plane Hyperbolic Geometry Revisited.Victor Pambuccian - 2011 - Studia Logica 97 (3):347 - 349.
    Using the axiom system provided by Carsten Augat in [1], it is shown that the only 6-variable statement among the axioms of the axiom system for plane hyperbolic geometry (in Tarski's language L B =), we had provided in [3], is superfluous. The resulting axiom system is the simplest possible one, in the sense that each axiom is a statement in prenex form about at most 5 points, and there is no axiom system consisting entirely of at most (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  33.  41
    The simplest axiom system for plane hyperbolic geometry.Victor Pambuccian - 2004 - Studia Logica 77 (3):385 - 411.
    We provide a quantifier-free axiom system for plane hyperbolic geometry in a language containing only absolute geometrically meaningful ternary operations (in the sense that they have the same interpretation in Euclidean geometry as well). Each axiom contains at most 4 variables. It is known that there is no axiom system for plane hyperbolic consisting of only prenex 3-variable axioms. Changing one of the axioms, one obtains an axiom system for plane Euclidean geometry, expressed in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  34. Les éléments vol. I : Introduction générale livres I-IV : Géométrie plane, « Bibliothèque d'histoire des sciences ». Euclide, Maurice Caveing & Bernard Vitrac - 1992 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 182 (1):110-112.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  34
    Analysis of contrasts and identifications of Burgers vectors for basal-plane dislocations and threading edge dislocations in 4H-SiC crystals observed by monochromatic synchrotron X-ray topography in grazing-incidence Bragg-case geometry.Hirofumi Matsuhata, Hirotaka Yamaguchi & Toshiyuki Ohno - 2012 - Philosophical Magazine 92 (36):4599-4617.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  10
    An expressive two-sorted spatial logic for plane projective geometry.Philippe Balbiani - 1998 - In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic. CSLI Publications. pp. 49-68.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  6
    An expressive two-sorted spatial logic for plane projective geometry.Philippe Balbiani - 1998 - In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic. CSLI Publications. pp. 49-68.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  21
    Corrigendum to “The complexity of plane hyperbolic incidence geometry is ∀∃∀∃”.Victor Pambuccian - 2008 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 54 (6):668-668.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Linguistic Geometry and its Applications.W. B. Vasantha Kandasamy, K. Ilanthenral & Florentin Smarandache - 2022 - Miami, FL, USA: Global Knowledge.
    The notion of linguistic geometry is defined in this book. It is pertinent to keep in the record that linguistic geometry differs from classical geometry. Many basic or fundamental concepts and notions of classical geometry are not true or extendable in the case of linguistic geometry. Hence, for simple illustration, facts like two distinct points in classical geometry always define a line passing through them; this is generally not true in linguistic geometry. Suppose (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  16
    Geometry as an extension of the group theory.A. Prusińska & L. Szczerba - 2002 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 10:131.
    Klein’s Erlangen program contains the postulate to study thegroup of automorphisms instead of a structure itself. This postulate, takenliterally, sometimes means a substantial loss of information. For example, thegroup of automorphisms of the field of rational numbers is trivial. Howeverin the case of Euclidean plane geometry the situation is different. We shallprove that the plane Euclidean geometry is mutually interpretable with theelementary theory of the group of authomorphisms of its standard model.Thus both theories differ practically in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  27
    Constructive geometry and the parallel postulate.Michael Beeson - 2016 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 22 (1):1-104.
    Euclidean geometry, as presented by Euclid, consists of straightedge-and-compass constructions and rigorous reasoning about the results of those constructions. We show that Euclidean geometry can be developed using only intuitionistic logic. This involves finding “uniform” constructions where normally a case distinction is used. For example, in finding a perpendicular to line L through point p, one usually uses two different constructions, “erecting” a perpendicular when p is on L, and “dropping” a perpendicular when p is not on L, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  31
    Geometry of time and space.Alfred Arthur Robb - 1936 - Cambridge [Eng.]: University Press.
    Alfred A. Robb. THEOREM 54 If P1 and P2 be a pair of parallel inertia planes while an inertia plane Q1 has parallel general lines a and b in common with P1 and P2 respectively and if Q2 be an inertia plane parallel to Q1 through some ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  43.  33
    The axioms of constructive geometry.Jan von Plato - 1995 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 76 (2):169-200.
    Elementary geometry can be axiomatized constructively by taking as primitive the concepts of the apartness of a point from a line and the convergence of two lines, instead of incidence and parallelism as in the classical axiomatizations. I first give the axioms of a general plane geometry of apartness and convergence. Constructive projective geometry is obtained by adding the principle that any two distinct lines converge, and affine geometry by adding a parallel line construction, etc. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  44.  14
    Geometry of the astrolabe in the tenth century.Abgrall Philippe - 2000 - Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 10 (1):7-77.
    Many studies on the astrolabe were written during the period from the ninth to the eleventh century, but very few of them related to projection, i.e., to the geometrical transformation underlying the design of the instrument. Among those that did, the treatise entitled The Art of the Astrolabe, written in the tenth century by Abū Sahl al-Qūhī, represents a particulary important phase in the history of geometry. This work recently appeared in a critical edition with translation and commentary by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  12
    LA GÉOMÉTRIE DE L'ASTROLABE AU X e SIÈCLE Geometry of the Astrolabe in the Tenth Century.Abgrall Philippe - 2000 - Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 10 (1):7-77.
    Many studies on the astrolabe were written during the period from the ninth to the eleventh century, but very few of them related to projection, i.e., to the geometrical transformation underlying the design of the instrument. Among those that did, the treatise entitled The Art of the Astrolabe, written in the tenth century by Abū Sahl al-Qūhī, represents a particulary important phase in the history of geometry. This work recently appeared in a critical edition with translation and commentary by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  60
    Thomas Reid’s geometry of visibles and the parallel postulate.Giovanni B. Grandi - 2005 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 36 (1):79-103.
    Thomas Reid (1710–1796) presented a two-dimensional geometry of the visual field in his Inquiry into the human mind (1764), whose axioms are different from those of Euclidean plane geometry. Reid’s ‘geometry of visibles’ is the same as the geometry of the surface of the sphere, described without reference to points and lines outside the surface itself. Interpreters of Reid seem to be divided in evaluating the significance of his geometry of visibles in the history (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  47.  57
    LA GÉOMÉTRIE DE L'ASTROLABE AU X e SIÈCLE Geometry of the Astrolabe in the Tenth Century.Abgrall Philippe - 2000 - Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 10 (1):7-77.
    Many studies on the astrolabe were written during the period from the ninth to the eleventh century, but very few of them related to projection, i.e., to the geometrical transformation underlying the design of the instrument. Among those that did, the treatise entitled The Art of the Astrolabe, written in the tenth century by Abu Sahl al-Quhi, represents a particulary important phase in the history of geometry. This work recently appeared in a critical edition with translation and commentary by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  24
    Visual Geometry of Classical Japanese Gardens.Gert Jakobus van Tonder - 2022 - Axiomathes 32 (5):841-868.
    The concept of geometry may evoke a world of pure platonic shapes, such as spheres and cubes, but a deeper understanding of visual experience demands insight into the perceptual organization of naturalistic form. Japanese gardens excel as designed environments where the complex fractal geometry of nature has been simplified to a structural core that retains the essential properties of the natural landscape, thereby presenting an ideal opportunity for investigating the geometry and perceptual significance of such naturalistic characteristics. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  9
    Affine Geometry and Relativity.Božidar Jovanović - 2023 - Foundations of Physics 53 (3):1-29.
    We present the basic concepts of space and time, the Galilean and pseudo-Euclidean geometry. We use an elementary geometric framework of affine spaces and groups of affine transformations to illustrate the natural relationship between classical mechanics and theory of relativity, which is quite often hidden, despite its fundamental importance. We have emphasized a passage from the group of Galilean motions to the group of Poincaré transformations of a plane. In particular, a 1-parametric family of natural deformations of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  16
    Some Interrelations between Geometry and Modal Logic.Ken Pledger - 2021 - Australasian Journal of Logic 18 (4).
    This is a reprinting of Ken Pledger’s PhD thesis, submitted to the University of Warsaw in 1980 with the degree awarded in 1981. It develops a one-sorted approach to the theory of plane geometry, based on the idea that the usually two-sorted theory “can be made one-sorted by keeping careful account of whether the incidence relation is iterated an even or odd number of times”.The one-sorted structures can also serve as Kripke frames for modal logics, and the thesis (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000